THE INDICATIONS OF IMMORTALITY
MAY be considered in two divisions: those which are independent of any theory respecting the Creator and his intentions,
and those which depend upon an antecedent belief on that subject.
Of the former class of arguments speculative men have in different ages put forward a considerable
variety of which those in the Phaedon of Plato are an example; but they are for the most part such as have no adherents, and
need not be seriously refuted, now. They are generally founded upon preconceived theories as to the nature of the thinking
principle in man, considered as distinct and separable from the body, and on other preconceived theories respecting death.
As, for example, that death, or dissolution, is always a separation of parts; and the soul being without parts, being simple
and indivisible, is not susceptible of this separation. Curiously enough, one of the interlocutors in the Phaedon anticipates
the answer by which an objector of the present day would meet this argument: namely, that thought and consciousness, though
mentally distinguishable from the body, may not be a substance separable from it, but a result of it, standing in a relation
to it (the illustration is Plato's) like that of a tune to the musical instrument on which it is played; and that the arguments
used to prove that the soul does not die with the body, would equally prove that the tune does not die with the instrument,
but survives its destruction and continues to exist apart. In fact, those moderns who dispute the evidences of the immortality
of the soul, do not, in general, believe the soul to be a substance per se, but
regard it as the name of a bundle of attributes, the attributes of feeling, thinking, reasoning, believing, willing, &c.,
and these attributes they regard as a consequence of the bodily organization, which therefore, they argue, it is as unreasonable
to suppose surviving when that organization is dispersed, as to suppose the colour or odour of a rose surviving when
the rose itself has perished. Those, therefore, who would deduce the immortality of the soul from its own nature have first
to prove that the attributes in question are not attributes of the body but of a separate substance. Now what is the
verdict of science on this point? It is not perfectly conclusive either way. In the first place, it does not prove, experimentally,
that any mode of organization has the power of producing feeling or thought. To make that proof good it would be necessary
that we should be able to produce an organism, and try whether it would feel; which we cannot do; organisms cannot by
any human means be produced, they can only be developed out of a previous organism. On the other hand, the evidence is
well nigh complete that all thought and feeling has some action of the bodily organism for its immediate antecedent or accompaniment;
that the specific variations and especially the different degrees of complication of the nervous and cerebral organization,
correspond to differences in the development of the mental faculties; and though we have no evidence, except negative,
that the mental consciousness ceases for ever when the functions of the brain are at an end, we do know that diseases of the
brain disturb the mental functions and that decay or weakness of the brain enfeebles them. We have therefore sufficient evidence
that cerebral action is, if not the cause, at least, in our present state of existence, a condition sine qua non of mental operations; and that assuming the mind to be a distinct substance, its separation from
the body would not be, as some have vainly flattered themselves, a liberation from trammels and restoration to freedom, but
would simply put a stop to its functions and remand it to unconsciousness, unless and until some other set of conditions supervenes,
capable of recalling it into activity, but of the existence of which experience does not give us the smallest indication.
. . .
The belief, however, in human immortality, in the minds of mankind generally, is probably not
grounded on any scientific arguments either physical or metaphysical, but on foundations with most minds much stronger,
namely on one hand the disagreeableness of giving up existence, (to those at least to whom it has hitherto been pleasant)
and on the other the general traditions of mankind. The natural tendency of belief to follow these two inducements, our
own wishes and the general assent of other people, has been in this instance reinforced by the utmost exertion of the power
of public and private teaching, rulers and instructors having at all times, with the view of giving greater effect to their
mandates whether from selfish or from public motives, encouraged to the utmost of their power the belief that there is a life
after death, in which pleasures and sufferings far greater than on earth, depend on our doing or leaving undone while alive,
what we are commanded to do in the name of the unseen powers. As causes of belief these various circumstances are most powerful.
As rational grounds of it they carry no weight at all.
That what is called the consoling nature of an opinion, that is, the pleasure we should have in
believing it to be true, can be a ground for believing it, is a doctrine irrational in itself and which would sanction half
the mischievous illusions recorded in history or which mislead individual life. It is sometimes, in the case now under
consideration, wrapt up in a quasi-scientific language. We are told that the desire of immortality is one of our instincts,
and that there is no instinct which has not corresponding to it a real object fitted to satisfy it. Where there is hunger
there is somewhere food, where there is sexual feeling there is somewhere sex, where there is love there is somewhere
something to be loved, and so forth: in like manner since there is the instinctive desire of eternal life, eternal life there
must be. The answer to this is patent on the very surface of the subject. It is unnecessary to go into any recondite considerations
concerning instincts, or to discuss whether the desire in question is an instinct or not. Granting that wherever there
is an instinct there exists something such as that instinct demands, can it be affirmed that this something exists in boundless
quantity, or sufficient to satisfy the infinite craving of human desires? What is called the desire of eternal life is simply
the desire of life; and does there not exist that which this desire calls for? Is there not life? And is not the instinct,
if it be an instinct, gratified by the possession and preservation of life? To suppose that the desire of life guarantees
to us personally the reality of life through all eternity, is like supposing that the desire of food assures us that we shall
always have as much as we can eat through our whole lives and as much longer as we can conceive our lives to be protracted
to.
The argument from tradition or the general belief of the human race, if we accept it as a guide
to our own belief, must be accepted entire: if so we are bound to believe that the souls of human beings not only survive
after death but show themselves as ghosts to the living, for we find no people who have had the one belief without the other.
Indeed it is probable that the former belief originated in the latter, and that primitive men would never have supposed
that the soul did not die with the body if they had not fancied that it visited them after death. Nothing could be more natural
than such a fancy; it is, in appearance, completely realized in dreams, which in Homer and in all ages like Homers, are supposed
to be real apparitions. To dreams we have to add not merely waking hallucinations but the delusions, however baseless,
of sight and hearing, or rather the misinterpretations of those senses, sight or hearing supplying mere hints from which imagination
paints a complete picture and invests it with reality. These delusions are not to be judged of by a modern standard: in early
times the line between imagination and perception was by no means clearly defined; there was little or none of the knowledge
we now possess of the actual course of nature, which makes us distrust or disbelieve any appearance which is at variance with
known laws. In the ignorance of men as to what were the limits of nature and what was or was not compatible with it, no one
thing seemed, as far as physical considerations went, to be much more improbable than another. In rejecting, therefore, as
we do, and as we have the best reason to do, the tales and legends of the actual appearance of disembodied spirits, we take
from under the general belief of mankind in a life after death, what in all probability was its chief ground and support,
and deprive it of even the very little value which the opinion of rude ages can ever have as evidence of truth. If it be said
that this belief has maintained itself in ages which have ceased to be rude and which reject the superstitions with which
it once was accompanied, the same may be said of many other opinions of rude ages, and especially on the most important and
interesting subjects, because it is on those subjects that the reigning opinion, whatever it may be, is the most sedulously
inculcated upon all who are born into the world. This particular opinion, moreover, if it has on the whole kept its ground,
has done so with a constantly increasing number of dissentients, and those especially among cultivated minds. Finally, those
cultivated minds which adhere to the belief ground it, we may reasonably suppose, not on the belief of others, but on arguments
and evidences; and those arguments and evidences, therefore, are what it concerns us to estimate and judge.
The preceding are a sufficient sample of the arguments for a future life which do not suppose
an antecedent belief in the existence, or any theory respecting the attributes of the Godhead. It remains to consider what
arguments are supplied by such lights, or such grounds of conjecture, as natural theology affords, on those great questions.
We have seen that these lights are but faint; that of the existence of a Creator they afford no
more than a preponderance of probability; of his benevolence a considerably less preponderance; that there is, however,
some reason to think that he cares for the pleasures of his creatures, but by no means that this is his sole care, or
that other purposes do not often take precedence of it. His intelligence must be adequate to the contrivances apparent in
the universe, but need not be more than adequate to them, and his power is not only not proved to be infinite, but the only
real evidences in natural theology tend to show that it is limited, contrivance being a mode of overcoming difficulties, and
always supposing difficulties to be overcome.
We have now to consider what inference can legitimately be drawn from these premises, in favor
of a future life. It seems to me, apart from express revelation, none at all.
The common arguments are, the goodness of God; the improbability that he would ordain the
annihilation of his noblest and richest work, after the greater part of its few years of life had been spent in the acquisition
of faculties which time is not allowed him to turn to fruit; and the special improbability that he would have implanted in
us an instinctive desire of eternal life, and doomed that desire to complete disappointment.
These might be arguments in a world the constitution of which made it possible without contradiction
to hold it for the work of a Being at once omnipotent and benevolent. But they are not arguments in a world like that in which
we live. The benevolence of the divine Being may be perfect, but his power being subject to unknown limitations, we know
not that he could have given us what we so confidently assert that he must have given; could
(that is) without sacrificing something more important. Even his benevolence, however justly inferred, is by no means
indicated as the interpretation of his whole purpose, and since we cannot tell how far other purposes may have interfered
with the exercise of his benevolence, we know not that he would, even if he could
have granted us eternal life. With regard to the supposed improbability of his having given the wish without its gratification,
the same answer may be made; the scheme which either limitation of power, or conflict of purposes, compelled him to adopt,
may have required that we should have the wish although it were not destined to
be gratified. One thing, however, is quite certain in respect to Gods government of the world; that he either could not, or
would not, grant to us every thing we wish. We wish for life, and he has granted some life: that we wish (or some of us wish)
for a boundless extent of life and that it is not granted, is no exception to the ordinary modes of his government. Many a
man would like to be a Croesus or an Augustus Caesar, but has his wishes gratified only to the moderate extent of a pound
a week or the Secretaryship of his Trades Union. There is, therefore, no assurance whatever of a life after death, on
grounds of natural religion.
|