The theory that Christianity could have begun without an historical
Jesus of Nazareth has been adamantly resisted by New Testament scholarship since it was first put forward some 200 years ago.
It has generally been held by a small minority of investigators, usually "outsiders." An important factor in this imbalance
has been the fact that, traditionally, the great majority working in the field of New Testament research have been religious
apologists, theologians, scholars who are products of divinity schools and university religion departments, not historians
per se. To suggest that a certain amount of negative bias may be operating among that majority where the debate over an historical
Jesus has been concerned, is simply to state the obvious. Nor is such a statement to be considered out of order, especially
in the face of the common 'argument' so often put forward against the mythicist position: that the vast majority of New Testament
scholars have always rejected the proposition of a non-existent Jesus, and continue to do so. In fact, the latter is simply
an "appeal to authority" and cannot by itself be given significant weight.
It is true that such a bias as may exist in traditional ranks does not automatically mean that they are wrong, or
that the mythicist viewpoint is correct. What we need to do is examine the negative position taken by the opposing side and
consider its substance. The problem is, traditional scholarship has offered very little of substance in opposing the theory
that Jesus never existed, and that is especially true in recent times. Even more progressive scholarship, such as the Jesus
Seminar, has never seriously addressed the question (other than an informal opinion poll among the Seminar's members when
it first began its work). Not a single first-rank critical scholar that I am aware of has devoted even an article to it, let
alone a book.
Something like The Evidence for Jesus (1986) by R. T. France, Vice-Principal of the London Bible College, hardly
fills that role, and is devoted to illuminating the figure of an historical Jesus—a largely orthodox one—not just
to defending his existence. As a defense it is quite ineffectual, taking no account (since it largely predates them) of recent
insights into Q, the pervasive midrashic content of Mark, the modeling of Mark's passion story on the traditional tale of
the Suffering Righteous One, and much else that has given ongoing support to the no-Jesus theory. Graham Stanton, in his The
Gospels and Jesus (1989), devotes a chapter to addressing the views of mythicist G. A. Wells. Stanton's 'case' against Wells' position is little
more than a citation of Josephus, Tacitus and Pliny (discussed below)—and an appeal to the authority that comes with
the majority's acceptance "that Jesus existed." Ian Wilson, in Jesus: The Evidence (1984), does much the same, first
acknowledging the uncertainty and contradiction in the early evidence, and then having recourse to the same trio of ancient
'witnesses.' All of them raise points that show little or no understanding for the depth and sophistication of the mythicist
position. J. D. G. Dunn, in his one-page "Note on Professor Wells' View" in The Evidence for Jesus (1985), falls back
on the old timeworn explanations for Paul's silence on a human figure. He, too, asks questions that show he is trapped within
the old paradigm and unable to grasp how standard objections to the mythicist position dissolve, as do many of the longstanding
problems in New Testament research, when the new paradigm of an evolving historical Jesus is applied to the evidence.
In the past fifteen years we have seen the orthodox Christian story systematically dismantled by critical scholarship
like that of the Jesus Seminar, many of whose members have become increasingly secular and scientific in their outlook, something
to be applauded. Insights into the dubious authenticity of Christian traditions, into the derivation of the Gospels and their
antecedents, into the Christian movement as it developed within the context of its time, have been coming with gathering speed,
not to mention radical positions on the historical Jesus that would have been unheard of little more than a decade ago. Within
such circles of modern scholarship one might expect a serious and comprehensive defense against the most threatening position
ever taken against the foundations of Christianity, one that is gaining an ever greater number of supporters and higher profile,
including in several recent books published in both North America and Europe. Yet none has been forthcoming. In the absence of such
a defense, an appeal to the majority viewpoint on the question of Jesus' existence is misplaced.
*
* *
*
The non-Christian witness to Jesus is anything but supportive of his existence. Until almost the end of the first
century, there is not a murmur of him in the Jewish or pagan record. The Alexandrian Jewish philosopher Philo, who lived until
about 50 CE and wrote of unusual sects like the Therapeutae and the Essenes, has nothing to say about Jesus or Christians.
Justus of Tiberias, a Jewish historian who wrote in Galilee in the 80s (his works are now lost), is reported later to have made no mention
whatever of Jesus. Pliny the Elder (died 79 CE) collected data on all manner of natural and astronomical phenomena, even those
which were legendary and which he himself did not necessarily regard as factual, but he records no prodigies associated with
the beliefs of Christians, such as an earthquake or darkening of the skies at a crucifixion, or any star of Bethlehem. The
first Roman satirist to scorn a sect which believed in a crucified Judean founder who had been a god was not Martial at the
end of the first century, nor Juvenal in the first half of the second century, but Lucian in the 160s. Reports of Epictetus,
the great Stoic philosopher of the early second century who preached universal brotherhood to the poor and humble masses,
record no knowledge on his part of a Jewish precursor. Nor does Seneca, the empire's leading ethicist during the reign of
Nero, make reference to such a figure. Other historians of the time, like Plutarch and Quintilian, are equally silent.
The famous passage about Jesus in chapter 18 of Josephus' Antiquities of the Jews (published around 93 CE),
the so-called "Testimonium Flavianum," is widely acknowledged to be, as it stands, a later Christian interpolation. It speaks
naively and devotionally of Jesus and declares him to have been the Messiah. Origen in the third century tells us that Josephus
did not believe in Jesus as the Messiah, a remark likely prompted by the fact that Josephus declared Vespasian the object
of the messianic prophecies (in Jewish War 6.5.4). This remark by Origen shows that the declaration in Antiquities
18 did not exist in his copy. But neither does Origen or anyone else before the 4th century mention any other reference
to Jesus here. Such a silence argues against the fallback claim that even though Christians later amended it, an original
reference to Jesus can be extracted from the present one. This "authentic residue" of the Testimonium would not only have
been positive enough to invite comment by such as Origen, it still contains opinions about Jesus that Josephus is unlikely
to have held. As for the passing identification in Antiquities 20 that "James" was the brother of Jesus known as the
Christ, there are problems in accepting this too as original to Josephus, such as his alleged use of the term "Christ" (Messiah),
a subject which Josephus shows sign of being reluctant to discuss in any of his works. Thus, the Josephan references have
too many problems to constitute reliable support for Jesus' existence. For a thorough examination of both Josephus' passages,
see Supplementary Article No. 10: Josephus Unbound: Reopening the Josephus Question.
The Roman historian Tacitus, in his Annals written around 115, makes the first pagan reference to Jesus as a man executed
in the reign of Tiberius. This is not likely to have been the result of a search of some archive, for the Romans hardly kept
records of the countless crucifixions around the empire going back almost a century. We have no evidence of such extensive
record-keeping. Besides, Tacitus is not known as a thorough researcher, which is illustrated by the fact that he gets Pilate's
title wrong, something that might have been corrected had he consulted an official record. Scholars such as Norman Perrin
(The New Testament: An Introduction, p.407) acknowledge that Tacitus' "information" probably came from local Christian
hearsay and police interrogation; this would have been at a time when the idea of an historical founder had recently taken
hold in Rome. There is even some reason to doubt the authenticity of this passage, despite its vilifying description of Christians.
The association of a persecution of Christians with the great fire in Nero's Rome (the context of Tacitus' reference) is nowhere
mentioned by Christian commentators for the next several centuries.
Pliny the Younger's well-known letter to Trajan, written from Asia Minor around 112 and asking the emperor for advice on
the prosecution of Christians, says nothing about a recent historical man, let alone biographical elements. "Christ," perhaps
a reference to the Jewish Messiah idea, is simply identified as a god in Christian worship. And the historian Suetonius' reference
(around 120) to "Chrestus" as someone, or some idea, that has produced agitation among Jews in Rome, is so flimsy and uncertain,
no secure meaning can be drawn from it, much less a connection to Christianity and an historical Jesus. It could be referring
to Jewish messianic expectation or to an early belief in a divine Christ.
There are those who appeal to obscure references in the historians Thallus and Phlegon about eclipses of the sun allegedly
associated with the crucifixion, but such pagan writers, their works now lost, come to us only through Christian commentators.
The latter could well have put their own spin on reports which originally had nothing to do with a Jesus, but simply referred
to an eclipse of the sun which astronomers date in the year 29. Certainly, there are no other reports at the time among either
Mediterranean writers or others around the world about a universal darkness at midday.
As for the references to Jesus in the Jewish Talmud: even though some remarks are attributed to rabbis who flourished
around the end of the first century (none earlier), they were not written down before the third century and later. Such records
cannot be relied upon to preserve authentic traditions of a few centuries earlier, ones that may have been influenced by,
or created in response to, Christian claims of the second century and later. In any case, such references are often so cryptic
and off the mark they can scarcely be identified with the Gospel figure. Some have him dying by stoning or hanging, rather
than by crucifixion. One places Jesus in the time of the Maccabean king Alexander Jannaeus around 100 BCE; another identifies the
husband of Jesus' mother as someone who is said to have been a contemporary of rabbi Akiba in the second century CE. All of
them allot responsibility for the death of this figure solely to the Jews, a strange situation in Jewish rabbinic tradition
if the Gospel story were history and widely known. As a witness to an historical Jesus, the Talmudic references are worthless.
*
* *
*
There are a number of fundamental problems in mainstream New Testament research that can be dealt with under the heading
of "Five Fallacies" which that research has traditionally been guilty of. (I will assume the reader's familiarity with Parts
One to Three.) The First Fallacy is the idea that Jews, both in Palestine and across the empire, could have come to
believe—or been converted to the idea by others— that a human man was the Son of God. Within a handful of years
of Jesus' supposed death we know of Christian communities all over the eastern Mediterranean, many of them involving at least
some Jewish adherents. Such Christians may have been numerous and troublesome enough in Rome to be expelled by Claudius
as early as the 40s. At the very least, Paul in Romans speaks of a congregation of the Christ that has been established in
the capital of the empire "for many years" (15:23). Traditional Christian views have maintained that such communities
were the product of dusty disciples from Judea who went off to centers big and small and almost overnight managed to convince
great numbers of Jews (as well as gentiles) that a humble preacher they had never seen or heard of, executed in Jerusalem
as a subversive, had risen from the dead, redeemed the world, and was in fact God's pre-existent Son who had helped him create
the universe. This is an incredible proposition.
I said in Part One that Judaism's fundamental theological tenet was: God is one. It is true that the first Jewish
Christians, such as Paul, were flirting with a compromise to monotheism in postulating a divine Son in heaven, even though
he was entirely spiritual in nature and was conceived of as a part of God; this Son was derived from scripture and was an
expression of the prominent philosophical idea of the age that the ultimate Deity gave off emanations of himself which served
as intermediaries with the world. But this is a far cry from turning a recent man who had walked the sands of Palestine into part of the Godhead.
(It was essentially gentiles who were later to create such an idea, and it produced the "parting of the ways" between the
Christian movement and its Jewish roots.) Almost any Jew would have reacted with apoplexy to the unprecedented message that
a man was God. In a society in which the utter separation of the divine from the human was an obsession, the Jewish God could
not be represented by even the suggestion of a human form, and thousands bared their necks before the swords of Pilate simply
to protest against the human images on Roman standards being brought into the city to overlook the Temple. To believe that
ordinary Jews were willing to bestow on any human man, no matter how impressive, all the titles of divinity and full identification
with the ancient God of Abraham is simply inconceivable.
Paul is not only assumed to have done this, but he did so without ever telling us that anyone challenged him on it,
that he had to defend such a blasphemous proposition. His comment in 1 Corinthians 1:23 that the cross of Christ is a "scandal"
refers to his idea that the divine Messiah had been crucified (a spiritual figure in a mythical setting), not that a recent
man was God.
The Second Fallacy is an extension of the first, and I touched on it in Part Three. Scholars are faced with a bewildering
variety of expression in earliest Christianity. Many circles of belief lacked fundamental Christian doctrines, and different
aspects of Jesus are said to have been preserved by separate groups. Modern critical scholarship has put forward a curious
scenario to explain all this. Various groups who came in contact with Jesus or the missionary movement about him are supposed
to have focused on different aspects of him, some exclusively on the teachings, others on the miracles, still others on the
message about his death and perceived resurrection as a redeeming act. Some came up with unique interpretations of him. Some
of these groups saw him in entirely human terms, while others, like Paul, turned him into God and abandoned all interest in
his pre-resurrection earthly life and identity. Burton Mack (in A Myth of Innocence, p.98f) suggests that this cultic
deification of Jesus took place under the influence of gentiles in Hellenistic circles like Antioch. But this hardly explains
Paul, allegedly a Jew born and bred, who was converted within two to five years of Jesus' supposed death. Did a whole Hellenistic
mythology develop around Jesus almost overnight, in the heart of Jerusalem—and Paul accepted it? Or did he not
believe in Jesus as the Son of God right from the start? Perhaps we are to view the theology of Paul's letters, our earliest
record written two decades later, as a result of the insidious influence of gentiles at Antioch.
Such scenarios fail to provide any convincing explanation for why such an immediate fragmentation would have taken
place, why the Christian movement began as "fluid and amorphous" (James Robinson in Trajectories Through Early Christianity,
p.114f). Mack admits that "much of the evidence is secondhand, and all of it is later." Out of a record of multiplicity, Christian
scholars have deduced a single founder and point of origin which is based on a later stage: the Gospel story, formed by the
postulated reconvergence of the original diverging strands. But no document records this initial phenomenon of differing "responses"
to the historical man, this break-up of Jesus into his component parts. Given a record whose earliest manifestation is nothing
but diversity, common sense requires us to assume the likelihood that this was in fact the incipient state, and that the new
faith arose in many different places with many different expressions. Some elements, such as the teachings, would have had
no connection to a Jesus in their early stages. Most of this diversity was later to be drawn together and recast under a composite
new figure, courtesy of the evangelists.
The above type of scenario involves a Third Fallacy. Scholars have long asked questions like that of Elizabeth Schlüsser-Fiorenza
("Wisdom Mythology and the Christological Hymns of the New Testament" in Aspects of Wisdom in Judaism and Early Christianity,
p.34): "Why do the hymns use the language of myth to speak of Jesus of Nazareth who was not a mythic figure but a concrete
historical person?" I pointed out in Part One that the very earliest expression about Jesus we find in the Christian record
presents him solely as a cosmic figure, the pre-existent creator and sustainer of the universe (Paul and his school), a heavenly
High Priest and Platonic Logos-type entity (Epistle to the Hebrews), a descending redeemer in the spiritual realm (the pre-Pauline
hymns), and so on. All such presentations of Jesus are said to be ways various circles adopted of "interpreting" the man Jesus
of Nazareth—according to sacred scripture and current philosophical and mythical concepts. But it would help if any
of these early writers gave us even a hint that such an intention was anywhere in their minds. How are we to understand an
"interpretation" when the thing supposedly being interpreted is never mentioned? John Knox (Myth and Truth, p.59) points
to Ephesians 1:3–10 as a kind of mythological drama created to explain Jesus, entirely in supernatural terms. Knox speaks
of "the remembered man Jesus" and "the wonder of his deeds and words." But where are these things in Ephesians 1:3–10,
or anywhere else? He says that the myth has been created based on memories of the Lord, but where are those memories? We cannot
accept Knox's claim that the myth in Ephesians is built upon "historical data" when that data is never pointed at or even
alluded to. A better explanation would be that the historical data has been added to the myth at a later time. The whole concept
that early Christian writers are "interpreting" Jesus of Nazareth even when they never mention him is a blatant "reading into"
the text on the part of those who must see the presumed historical figure behind all this scriptural and mythological presentation.
Scholars, in seeking an explanation for Paul's blanket silence on the historical Jesus, have given us a Fourth Fallacy.
They rationalize that Paul "had no interest" in Jesus' earthly incarnation, that his theology did not require it. This is
difficult to fathom. Paul's faith is centered on the crucifixion. What bizarre mental processes could have led him to disembody
it, to completely detach it from its historical time and place, from the life which culminated on Calvary? Why would he transplant
the great redeeming act to some mythological realm of demonic powers who were responsible for "crucifying the Lord of glory"
(1 Corinthians 2:8)? Why would he give Christ "significance only as a transcendent divine being" (Herman Ridderbos, Paul
and Jesus, p.3)?
And what of the details of Jesus' life? Could Pilate not have served Paul as an example of the "wisdom of the world"
which could not understand the "wisdom of God"? For Paul, baptism is the prime sacrament of Christian ritual; through it believers
receive the Spirit and are adopted as sons of God. Yet we are to assume that Paul, in presenting his baptismal rite (such
as in Romans 6), cared nothing about Jesus' own baptism by John, about such traditions that he had received the Spirit in
the form of a dove, that he had been adopted as Son by the Father in the voice from heaven. We are to assume that in all the
bitter debates he engaged in through his letters, such as on the validity of the Jewish dietary laws, Paul never felt a need
to introduce the Lord's own actions and teachings concerning the subjects under dispute. Are we to accept, too, that Jesus'
earthly signs and wonders would not have been an incalculable selling point to gentiles, immersed as they were in popular
pagan traditions of the wonder-working "divine man," a concept which fitted the earthly career of Jesus to a "T"? And are
we to believe that, even if Paul had expunged Christ's human life from his own mind, his audiences and converts likewise felt
no interest and did not press him for details of Jesus' earthly sayings and deeds—something of which he shows no sign
in his letters? In any event, explanations for Paul's silence and lack of interest would have to apply to all the other early
epistle writers, who are equally silent—a situation so extraordinary as to defy rationalization. Amid such considerations,
the argument from silence becomes legitimate and compelling.
Finally, many today find increasingly acceptable the direction which most recent liberal scholarship seems to be following:
that Jesus was only a man, a Jewish preacher who was somehow divinized after his death, a death which did not result in resurrection.
But here it seems that they face an insurmountable dilemma, a Fifth Fallacy. First of all, such a divinization on the scale
that Jesus underwent would have been unprecedented, and there is no more unlikely milieu for this to have happened in than
a Jewish one. Nor is this divinization gradual, a graph line which ascends as his reputation grows, as the things he did in
his life took on magnified stature and interpretation. Rather, at the earliest we can see any evidence for it, Jesus is already
at the highest point, cast in an entirely mythological picture: fully divine, pre-existent before the creation of the world,
moving in the celestial spheres and grappling with the demonic forces. Those deeds of his life which should have contributed
to such an elevation are nowhere in evidence.
Let's put the dilemma this way: If this man Jesus had had the explosive effect on his followers that is said of him,
and on the thousands of believers who responded so readily to the message about him, such a man would have had to blaze in
the firmament of his time. That impact would have been based on the force of his personality, on the unique things he said
and did. There is no other way.
And yet the picture we see immediately after Jesus' death, and for the next two generations in every extant document,
flatly contradicts this. The blazing star immediately drops out of sight. No contemporary historian, philosopher or popular
writer records him. There is no sign of any tradition or phenomenon associated with him. For over half a century Christian
writers themselves totally ignore his life and ministry. Not a saying is quoted and attributed to him. Not a miracle is marveled
at. No aspect of his human personality, anchored within any biographical setting, is ever referred to. The details of his
life, the places of his career: they raise no interest in any of his believers. This is an eclipse that does not even grant
us a trace of a corona!
If, on the other hand, Jesus was simply an ordinary human man, a humble (if somewhat charismatic) Jewish preacher,
who really said little of what has been imputed to him, who performed no real miracles, and who of course did not rise from
the dead—all of which might explain why he attracted no great attention and could have his life ignored as unimportant
by his later followers—what, then, is the explanation for how such a life and personality could have given rise to the
vast range of response the scholars postulate, to the cosmic theology about him, to the conviction that he had risen from
the dead, to the unstoppable movement which early Christianity seems to have been? This is an unsolvable dilemma.
If all we have in the earliest Christian record is this cosmic divine figure who moves in mythological spheres—just
like all the other savior deities of the day—are we not compelled by scientific principles to accept that this and no
more was the object of early Christian worship? If, to support this, we can present within the evidence a logical process
by which such a figure can be seen to take on a biography and a place in history, do we have any justification for continuing
to maintain that the divine, cosmic Christ grew out of the human Jesus of Nazareth?
*
* *
*
THE SECOND CENTURY APOLOGISTS
The Christian Apologists of the second century present us with a dramatic picture of continuing diversity
in the Christian movement and, among most of them, a surprising and revealing silence on Jesus of Nazareth.
The first 100 years of Christianity have received the greatest attention from Christian scholarship. Within the period
up to about 130, so conventional wisdom has it, lie Jesus himself and the origins of the church, as well as all the documents
which ended up in the canon of the New Testament. Also included are the surviving writings by that varied group known as the
Apostolic Fathers, which reveal some of the internal conditions and conflicts within the growing movement. The period following,
and running for another 100 years or so, was the age of the Apologists. These were men like Justin Martyr who presented and
justified Christianity to an outside world which was largely hostile to the new faith.
In Parts One to Three of the Main Articles, I provided a picture of the origins and growth of Christianity which rejects
the existence of an historical Jesus of Nazareth. One of the key features of that picture is the unusual diversity of expression
to be found in the early Christian record: about the figure of Jesus, about Christian theology, ritual practice and views
of salvation. This diversity points not to a human founder and single missionary movement proceeding out of him, but to a
widespread and uncoordinated religious movement founded on various beliefs in a divine, intermediary Son of God, a wholly
spiritual entity. A related feature is the virtually universal silence in that early record on anything to do with the human
man and events known to us from the Gospels.
What do we find as Christianity enters its second 100 years? In fact, we find more of the same. Those who have studied
the apologists have tended to make some surprising observations. They note how little continuity these writers show with earlier
traditions. Their ideas often have nothing in common with those of the New Testament epistles and even the Gospels. There
is no dependence on Paul. Moreover, such writers seem not to move in ecclesiastical circles. Even Justin, though he worked
in Rome, has nothing to say about bishops and church
organizations. And almost all of them before the year 180 (Justin being the major exception) are silent on the Gospels and
the figure of Jesus contained in them. In fact, one could say that they pointedly ignore any historical figure at all.
This astonishing state of affairs, taken with the fact that the Gospels and the Acts of the Apostles show no sign
of surfacing in any other Christian writers until the middle of the second century, supports the conclusion that the figure
of Jesus of Nazareth was a development in Christian thought which came to life only in the Gospels and gradually, throughout
the course of the second century, imposed itself on the movement as a whole.
Let's take a closer look at the evidence supplied by the Christian apologists.
Scholars specializing in the second century have characterized the Christianity of the apologists as essentially a
philosophical movement. Whereas the premier expression of Christian development in the first century, the one centered around
Paul and his circles, was an apocalyptically oriented phenomenon with a strong Jewish flavor and preaching a dying savior,
that of the apologists, who were all located in cosmopolitan centers across much of the empire, was grounded in Platonic philosophy
and Hellenistic Judaism.
Justin, the apologist about whom we know the most, came to Christianity after having investigated all the other popular
philosophies of his day: the Stoics, Peripatetics (based on Aristotle), the Pythagoreans. Finally, he was schooled in Middle
Platonism, the predominant philosophical outlook of the era which colored everything else, especially in its strongly religious
concerns about the nature of the Deity and its relation to humanity. When Justin encountered Christianity, he judged it the
best version of contemporary philosophy. In Rome, he seems to have had no connection with any ecclesiastical
body, but set up his own school, teaching Christian philosophy in the manner of pagan philosophers of the time.
And what was this 'Christian philosophy' as presented by the apologists as a group? There is no question that it had
roots in Jewish ideas. It preached the monotheistic worship of the Jewish God, a God touted as superior to those of the pagans.
For information about this God it looked to the Hebrew scriptures. It placed great value on a mode of life founded on Jewish
ethics; again, something touted as superior to the ethical philosophy of the pagans. At the same time, it derived from Platonism
the concept of a Son of God, a 'second God' or Logos (Word), a force active in the world and serving as an intermediary between
God and humanity. This idea of the Logos was floating in the air of most Greek philosophies and even Hellenistic Judaism.
Thus the religion of the apologists has been styled "Platonic-biblical" or "religious Platonism with a Judaistic cast."
It would seem to have grown out of Jewish Diaspora circles which had immersed themselves in Greek philosophy. (Justin and
others, including the movement known as Gnosticism, provide evidence of heretical Jewish sects, with many gentiles attached,
which had evolved a great distance from traditional Jewish thinking.) There is little to suggest that this religion proceeded
out of the first century branch of Christian development surrounding Paul. There is none of Paul's or the Gospels' focus on
the Messiah/Christ or the end of the world, and the apologists' views of salvation are rooted in Greek mysticism, not Jewish
martyrology for sin. Instead, the two expressions seem like separate branches of a very broad tree.
Justin, and whoever recast the Gospel of John to include the Prologue, with its hymn equating the Logos with Jesus,
came to believe that the intermediary Word, the spiritual Son of God, had been incarnated in a human figure as recounted in
the Gospels. But is this true of the apologists as a whole? The amazing fact is, that of the five or six major apologists
up to the year 180 (after that, Irenaeus, Tertullian, Clement of Alexandria and Origen are all firmly anchored in Gospel tradition),
none, with the exception of Justin, introduces an historical Jesus into their defences of Christianity to the pagans.
Consider Theophilus of Antioch. According to Eusebius, he became bishop
of the Christian community in that city in 168, but one has to wonder. In his treatise To Autolycus, apparently written
toward the year 180, he tells us that he was born a pagan and became a Christian after reading the Jewish scriptures, a situation
common to virtually all the apologists.
But what, for Theophilus, is the meaning of the name "Christian"? The Autolycus of the title has asked him this question.
He answers (I.12): "Because we are anointed with the oil of God." (The name "Christ" itself means Anointed One, from the anointed
kings of Israel.) In fact, Theophilus never mentions Christ, or Jesus, at all! He makes no
reference to a founder-teacher; instead, Christians have their doctrines and knowledge of God through the Holy Spirit. Along
with the pronouncements of the Old Testament prophets, he includes "the gospels" (III.12), but these too are the inspired word
of God, not a record of Jesus' words and deeds. When he quotes ethical maxims corresponding to Jesus' Gospel teachings, he
presents them (II.14) as the teaching of these gospels, not of Jesus himself.
And what is Theophilus' Son of God? He is the Word through whom God created the world, who was begat by him along
with Wisdom (II.10). He is the governing principle and Lord of all creation, inspiring the prophets and the world in general
to a knowledge of God. Yet Theophilus has not a thing to say about this Word's incarnation into flesh, or any deed performed
by him on earth. In fact, he hastens to say (II.22) that this is not a Son in the sense of begetting, but as innate in the
heart of God. Here he seems to quote part of the opening lines of the Gospel of John, the Word as God and instrumental in
creation, but nothing else. Is this from the full-blown Gospel, or perhaps from the Logos hymn John drew upon? (The name "John",
the only evangelist mentioned, could be a later marginal gloss inserted into the text; but see below.) Such writers, Theophilus
says, are inspired men, not witnesses to an historical Jesus.
As for redemption, all will gain eternal life who are obedient to the commandments of God (II.27). There is no concept
in Theophilus of an atoning sacrificial death of Jesus, a death he never mentions. And when challenged on his doctrine that
the dead will be raised (Autolycus has demanded: "Show me even one who has been raised from the dead!"), this Christian has
not a word to say about Jesus' own resurrection. He even accuses the pagans of worshiping "dead men" (I.9) and ridicules them
for believing that Hercules and Aesclepius were raised from the dead (I.13). All this, in answer to an Autolycus who has asked:
"Show me thy God."
Athenagoras of Athens, who worked in Alexandria, wrote around the same time,
though one ancient witness places him a few decades earlier. He was a philosopher who had embraced Christianity, but he shows
no involvement in any church, or interest in rituals and sacraments. In A Plea For the Christians addressed to the
emperor, he says this of his new beliefs (10): "We acknowledge one God . . . by whom the Universe has been created through
his Logos, and set in order and kept in being . . . for we acknowledge also a Son of God . . . If it occurs to you to
enquire what is meant by the Son, I will state that he is the first product of the Father (who) had the Logos in himself.
He came forth to be the idea and energizing power of all material things."
Unfortunately, in the course of 37 chapters, Athenagoras neglects to tell the emperor that Christians believe this
Logos to have been incarnated in the person of Jesus of Nazareth. He dissects contemporary Platonic and Stoic philosophy,
angels and demons, as well as details of various Greek myths, but he offers not a scrap about the life of the Savior. He presents
(11) Christian doctrine as things "not from a human source, but uttered and taught by God," and proceeds to quote ethical
maxims very close to parts of the Sermon on the Mount: "Love your enemies; bless them that curse you . . . ." Other quotations
he labels as coming from scripture, or from "our teaching." Are these ethical collections that are unattributed to Jesus?
Athenagoras never uses the term "gospel"; he speaks of "the witness to God and the things of God" and enumerates the prophets
and other men, yet he ignores what should have been the greatest witness of them all, Jesus of Nazareth.
With no incarnation, there is in Athenagoras' presentation of the Christian faith no death and resurrection of Jesus,
no sacrifice and Atonement. Eternal life is gained "by this one thing alone: that (we) know God and his Logos" (12). In fact,
the names Jesus and Christ never appear in Athenagoras. Yet he can say (11), "If I go minutely into the particulars of our
doctrines, let it not surprise you." One might be forgiven for regarding this as blatant dishonesty.
The anonymous Epistle to Diognetus is often included with the Apostolic Fathers.
But it is really an apology, a defence of Christianity addressed probably to an emperor, either Hadrian or Marcus Aurelius.
Most scholars lean to the earlier date (c.130). The writer goes so far as to say that the ultimate God sent the Logos, his
Son, down to earth, but no time, place, or identity for this incarnation are provided. The name Jesus never appears. The Son
revealed God, but is not portrayed as a human teacher.
We find an allusion (9) to the Atonement: "He (God) took our sins upon himself and gave his own Son as a ransom for
us," but his description of this act is based on scripture. No Gospel details are mentioned, no manner of the Son's death
(if that's what it was), no resurrection. All this is in response to Diognetus' "close and careful inquiries" about the Christian
religion. (The final two chapters of the sole surviving manuscript, which contain a reference to apostles and disciples of
the Word, have been identified as belonging to a separate document, probably a homily from the mid to late second century.)
We turn now to Tatian, a pupil of Justin. He was converted to Christianity, he says, by reading the Jewish scriptures.
At a later stage of his career, after apostatizing to the heretical sect of the Encratites and going off to Syria, Tatian composed the Diatessaron,
the first known harmony of the four canonical Gospels. But while still in Rome,
sometime around 160, he wrote an Apology to the Greeks, urging pagan readers to turn to the truth. In this description
of Christian truth, Tatian uses neither "Jesus" nor "Christ" nor even the name "Christian." Much space is devoted to outlining
the Logos, the creative power of the universe, first-begotten of the Father, through whom the world was made—but none
to the incarnation of this Logos. His musings on God and the Logos, rather than being allusions to the Gospel of John, as
some claim, contradict the Johannine Prologue in some respects and may reflect Logos commonplaces of the time. Resurrection
of the dead is not supported by Jesus' resurrection. Eternal life is gained through knowledge of God (13:1), not by any atoning
sacrifice of Jesus.
In Tatian's Apology we find a few allusions to Gospel sayings, but no specific
reference to written Gospels and no attribution of such things to Jesus. Instead, all knowledge comes from God himself. Tatian
says he was "God-taught" (29:2). He does, however, make a revealing comment about mythical stories, which I will return to
in a moment. Finally, around the year 155, the first Latin apologist, Minucius Felix, wrote a dialogue between a Christian
and a heathen, entitled Octavius. It too presents a Christianity without an historical Jesus, and in fact contains
some startling features in this regard. I will examine it in some detail in the latter part of this article.
* *
* *
Something extremely odd is going on here. If one leaves aside Justin, there is a silence in the second century apologists
on the subject of the historical Jesus which is almost the equal to that in the first century letter writers. Commentators
on these works, like those studying the earlier epistles, have scrambled to come up with explanations.
One is that the apologists were concerned first and foremost with preaching the monotheistic Father, the God of the
Jews, while debunking the Greek myths with their all-too-human and morally uninspiring divinities. This is true. But it should
not preclude them from devoting some space to the most essential feature of the faith, and besides, the apologists have no
reluctance about bringing in the Son of God in the form of the Logos. In fact, the apologists as a group profess a faith which
is nothing so much as a Logos religion. It is in essence Platonism carried to its fullest religious implications and wedded
with Jewish theology and ethics. The figure of Jesus of Nazareth as the incarnation of the Logos is a graft, an adoption which
was embraced only by Justin.
Of course, the glaring anomaly which must be explained is this: how can an apologist be giving his pagan readers a
meaningful picture of the Christian faith when he leaves out the most central of its elements, the figure of Jesus and what
he had done for salvation? How was the reader to understand the history and origins of the movement without him?
Inevitably, commentators have been led to conclude that the omission—indeed, the suppression—of Jesus
was deliberate. Pagan philosophers like Galen had challenged Christian thinkers that their faith was based on revelation rather
than reasoned philosophical argument. They had ridiculed the idea of a crucified god. The heathen attitude had made it impolitic
to speak of Jesus of Nazareth, and so he needed to be kept in the closet.
Too many common sense arguments tell against this 'explanation.' First, a writer like
Athenagoras is quite adept at reasoned, sophisticated argument. Why not apply such talents to a justification of Christianity's
principal tenet? If the world at large is maligning Jesus, surely the overriding need is to rehabilitate him, not hide him
away. Second, this suppression of Jesus, the misrepresentation of everything from the name "Christian" to the source of Christian
ethics, amounts to nothing less than a denial of Christ. The apologist is constructing a picture which excludes the
central elements of the faith, falsifying his presentation, leaving no room for Jesus. He has gone beyond silence in stating,
"I have said all there is to say." In an age when Christian pride and fortitude required that any penalty be faced—even
the ultimate one—rather than renounce the faith, this gutting of Christian doctrine would have smacked of betrayal.
It would have horrified believers and quickly discredited the apologists in Christian eyes. Could any of them really have
chosen to defend the Name by expunging it?
And who would they be fooling? Any pagan who knew the first thing about Christianity would surely be familiar with
the figure of Jesus of Nazareth as the movement's founder. An 'apology' for the faith which left him out would readily be
seen for the sham that it was, thus foiling the whole object of the exercise. Besides, Justin, the most prominent of the apologists,
felt no such qualms about placing Jesus at the center of his exposition. Tatian was someone who cared not a fig for the objections
or sensibilities of any pagan. And beyond the year 180 no Christian writer felt any need or pressure to suppress Jesus.
Another important consideration is that the apologists are touting the superiority of Christian ethics and its monotheistic
view of God. If Jesus had been the source of these teachings, their stature would have been raised by being presented as the
product of a great teacher; while at the same time, the attribution to Jesus of this estimable body of ethics and theology
would have gone a long way toward redeeming him in pagan eyes for whatever else Christians might have been claiming about
him. The fact that no one but Justin has incorporated the teaching, human Jesus into his appeals to the pagan is too bizarre
a situation. No, some other explanation for the silence of the bulk of the apologetic movement must be sought.
A clue to the solution of this puzzle lies in Tatian's Apology. In chapter 21 he says, "We are not fools,
men of Greece, when we declare that God has been born in
the form of man (his only allusion to the incarnation) . . . Compare your own stories with our narratives." He goes on to
describe some of the Greek myths about gods come to earth, undergoing suffering and even death for the benefaction of mankind.
"Take a look at your own records and accept us merely on the grounds that we too tell stories."
This may well be a reference to the Christian Gospels. But if he can allude to the incarnation
in this way, why does he not deal with it openly and at length? His comment is hardly a ringing endorsement, or a declaration
that such stories are to be accepted as history. The way Tatian compares them to the Greek myths implies that he regards them
as being on the same level. Certainly, he does not rush to point out that the Christian stories are superior or, unlike the
Greek ones, factually true. Nor can we get around the fact that Tatian pointedly ignores those Gospel stories in the rest
of his Apology. (He was to change his mind by the time he composed the Diatessaron.) Furthermore, he ignores
them even though his language clearly implies that the pagans were familiar with them.
There seems to be only one way to interpret all this. We can assume that the philosopher-apologists were familiar
with the Gospel story and its figure of Jesus of Nazareth. But, with the exception of Justin, they have chosen not to integrate
these elements into their own faith, not to identify this reputed historical founder-teacher with their divine Logos and Son
of God, not to regard him as the source of Christian teachings.
This is possible only if the Logos religion the apologists subscribed to, especially at the time of their conversion,
was lacking the figure of Jesus of Nazareth. Only if they could view the Gospel story and its central character as a recent
graft, a fictional tale like those of the Greeks, was it possible for them to reject it, to feel that they could be presenting
the Christian faith legitimately. Only if they felt it were possible for pagans to accept the story of Jesus as a myth like
their own religious myths, was it acceptable for the apologists to present to them a Christianity which ignored or rejected
the figure of Jesus.
As a mix of Platonism and Hellenistic Judaism, the apologists' branch of Christianity had become prominent throughout
the empire in the second century. (Paulinism had gone into eclipse until the ascendancy of the church of Rome and its rehabilitation
of Paul as the latter half of the century progressed.) As we have seen, this Platonic Christianity defined itself in ways
which had nothing to do with an historical Jesus. Nor is it likely to have grown out of Paulinism, as they have virtually
nothing in common.
If development had been as the scholars like to present it, a shift in emphasis from
the 'Palestinian' style of Christianity to one based on Greek philosophy and Hellenistic Judaism, the figure of Jesus would
hardly have been dropped; he would have been integrated into the Platonic picture. This is not a Christian 'utilization' of
Greek philosophy. The apologists' faith is the religious Platonism of the time brought into a Jewish theological
and ethical setting (which rendered the Logos and the faith "anointed" or Christian). It is significant that none of them
(possibly excepting Theophilus) have connections with a church.
Such a picture supports the view that Christianity, for its first 150 years, was a mosaic of uncoordinated expressions.
It was a variegated organism which took root and flowered across the landscape of the empire, a widely divergent mix of Jewish
and Greek features. As time went on, the distillation of Jesus of Nazareth out of certain pores in this organism spread inexorably
across its entire surface, until by the year 200 he was firmly entrenched in every aspect of the faith.
Even Justin gives evidence of this picture. After reaching Rome in the
140s, he encountered some of the Gospels and embraced the historical man-god they told of. In his apologetic writings, penned
in the 150s, Jesus and the Gospels occupy center stage. For Justin, the Word/Logos "took shape, became man, and was called
Jesus Christ" (Apology, 5). But he has left us an inadvertent record of the nature of the faith he joined before
his encounter with the story of a human Jesus.
The Dialogue with the Jew Trypho was written after the Apology, and
the latter can be dated to the early 150s. But the action of Trypho is set at the time of the Second Jewish Revolt,
in the 130s, and scholars are confident that this represents the time of Justin's conversion, which he describes in the opening
chapters.
By the sea near Ephesus Justin encounters an old man, a Christian philosopher. After a discussion of the joys and
benefits of philosophy, the old man tells of ancient Jewish prophets who spoke by the Divine Spirit. These prophets, he says,
had proclaimed the glory of God the Father and his Son, the Christ. (This was the interpretation of the Hebrew Bible in Platonic
terms.) Wisdom could come only to those who have it imparted to them by God and his Christ.
At this, says Justin (8:1), "a flame was kindled in my soul; and a love of the prophets and of those who are friends
of Christ possessed me." Justin does not even say (despite the best attempts of some commentators) that he felt a love for
Christ himself, for in the Christianity to which he was converted, Christ was a philosophical concept. He was a part of the
Godhead in heaven, a Logos-type entity. This Christ is a Savior by virtue of the wisdom he imparts (8:2). This is Justin's
concept of salvation here, for he goes on to conclude the story of his conversion by saying to Trypho: "If you are eagerly
looking for salvation, and if you believe in God, you may become acquainted with the Christ of God and, after being initiated,
live a happy life." (Later, under the influence of the Gospels, Justin laid increasing emphasis on the redeeming value of
Christ's death and resurrection, but in the basic Logos religion the Son saves by revealing God.)
Where is Jesus of Nazareth in all this? The old philosopher had not a word to say about
him, nor about any incarnation of the Son. We are fortunate that Justin did not recast the memory of his conversion experience
in the light of his later beliefs based on the Gospels. In those opening chapters of the Dialogue with the Jew Trypho
we can see that all the apologists came to the same Christian faith: a Platonic religious philosophy grounded in Hellenistic
Judaism which fails to include any historical Jesus.
Trypho himself may be a literary invention, but Justin puts into his mouth (8:6) a telling
accusation, one which must have represented a common opinion of the time: "But Christ—if he has indeed been born, and
exists anywhere—is unknown . . . And you, having accepted a groundless report, invent a Christ for yourselves . . .
" Trypho also expresses the opinion that the incarnation is incredible and even Justin admits (Apology, 13) that
"sober-minded men" are of the opinion that "Christians are mad to give a crucified man second place to God." As we shall see,
even some Christians were in agreement.
In passing, I will mention that perhaps the earliest surviving apology, that of Aristides to the emperor Antoninus
Pius, a short and minor work written in Syriac around 140, is clearly dependent on some Gospel account. It speaks of God born
of a virgin, having twelve disciples, pierced died and buried, then rising after three days. This apology comes from a different
milieu, one located in the Palestine-Syria area (where the Synoptic Gospels were written), for it has nothing to say about
the Logos or Greek philosophical concepts.
* *
* *
I have left until last the most fascinating of all the apologies, a document which could well be called a 'smoking
gun.' The little treatise Octavius was written in Rome, or possibly North Africa, in Latin. It takes the form of a debate
between Caecilius, a pagan, and Octavius, a Christian, chaired and narrated by the author, Minucius Felix, by whose name the
work is now usually referred to.
There has been a long and seesaw debate as to when Minucius Felix was written.
A clear literary relationship exists with Tertullian's much longer Apology, written around the year 200. But who
borrowed from whom? A good general rule says that the later writer tends to expand on what the earlier writer wrote, not chop
drastically, especially since in this case it would mean that Minucius Felix had cut out many important Christian dogmas and
every single reference to the Gospel Jesus—and this, well into the third century, when no one else had any qualms about
speaking of such things. This and other arguments considered, the earlier dating between 150 and 160 is much preferable. (See
H. J. Baylis, Minucius Felix [1928], p.273.)
In this debate, the names of Christ and Jesus are never used, though the word "Christian" appears throughout. Nor
is there any allusion to the Son or Logos. Octavius' Christianity revolves around the Unity and Providence of God and the
rejection of all pagan deities, the resurrection of the body and its future reward or punishment. In regard to the latter,
no appeal is made to Jesus' own resurrection as proof of God's ability and intention to resurrect the dead. Not even in answer
to the challenge (11): "What single individual has returned from the dead, that we might believe it for an example?" Much
of Octavius' argument is devoted to countering the calumnies against Christians which Caecilius, representing general pagan
opinion, enumerates: everything from debauchery to the devouring of infants, to Christian secrecy and hopes for the world's
fiery destruction.
But here is where it gets interesting. For no other apologist but Justin has voiced and dealt with one particular
accusation which the writer puts into the mouth of Caecilius. The list of calumnies in chapter 9 runs like this (partly paraphrased):
"This abominable congregation should be
rooted out . . . a religion of lust and fornication. They reverence the head of an ass . . . even the genitals of their priests
. . . . And some say that the objects of their worship include a man who suffered death as a criminal, as well as the
wretched wood of his cross; these are fitting altars for such depraved people, and they worship what they deserve . .
. . Also, during initiations they slay and dismember an infant and drink its blood . . . at their ritual feasts they indulge
in shameless copulation."
Remember that a Christian is composing this passage. (The sentence in italics is translated in full.) He has included
the central element and figure of the Christian faith, the person and crucifixion of Jesus, within a litany of ridiculous
and unspeakable calumnies leveled against his religion—with no indication, by his language or tone, that this reference
to a crucified man is to be regarded as in any way different from the rest of the items: disreputable accusations which need
to be refuted. Could a Christian author who believed in a crucified Jesus and his divinity really have been capable of this
manner of presentation?
In Octavius' half of the debate, he proceeds eventually to the refutation of these slanders. Here are some of the
other things he says along the way.
In ridiculing the Greek myths about the deaths of their gods, such as Isis lamenting over the dismembered Osiris, he
says (22): "Is it not absurd to bewail what you worship, or worship what you bewail?" In other words, he is castigating the
Greeks for lamenting and worshiping a god who is slain. Later he says (23): "Men who have died cannot become gods, because
a god cannot die; nor can men who are born (become gods) . . . Why, I pray, are gods not born today, if such have ever been
born?" He then goes on to ridicule the whole idea of gods procreating themselves, which would include the idea of a god begetting
a son. Elsewhere (20) he scorns those who are credulous enough to believe in miracles performed by gods.
How, without any saving qualification, could a Christian put such arguments forward,
since they would confute and confound essential Christian beliefs in his own mind, and leave himself open to the
charge of hypocrisy? It is one thing for the puzzled commentator to claim that silences in the apologists are due to a desire
not to discourage or irritate the pagans with long and confusing theological treatises on subjects they are prejudiced against,
or because they are not aiming to provide a comprehensive picture of the faith. But when an apologist makes statements which
flatly contradict and even calumnize ideas which should be at the very heart of his own beliefs and personal devotion, such
explanations are clearly discredited.
And how does Minucius Felix deal with the accusation that Christians worship a crucified man and his cross? As he
did in Caecilius' diatribe, the author inserts his response into the midst of his refutation of other calumnies about incestuous
banquets and adoration of a priest's genitals. Here is the manner and context in which he deals with the charge of worshiping
a crucified criminal (29):
"1These
and similar indecencies we do not wish to hear; it is disgraceful having to defend ourselves from such charges. People who
live a chaste and virtuous life are falsely charged by you with acts which we would not consider possible, except that we
see you doing them yourselves. 2Moreover (nam), when you attribute to our religion
the worship of a criminal and his cross, you wander far from the truth in thinking that a criminal deserved, or that a mortal
man could be able, to be believed in as God. 3Miserable indeed is that man whose whole hope is dependent
on a mortal, for such hope ceases with his (the latter's) death . . . ."
Before going on, we should first note that
verse 2, following as it does on the sentiments of verse 1 (which the Latin word nam emphasizes), makes it clear
that the writer regards this accusation as being in the same vein as the other "indecencies" he is at pains to refute. And
what is the refutation he provides? It is to heap scorn on those who would believe that a crucified criminal, a mortal, should
be thought of as a god. Where is the necessary qualification that no Christian could surely have remained silent on? Where
is the saving defence that in fact this crucified man was not a mortal, but was indeed God? Some claim that this is what Minucius
is implying, but such an implication is so opaque, it can only be derived from reading it into the text. Octavius' words certainly
do not contain it, although they do imply that the writer knows of some Christians who believe such things, but he has no
sympathy with them.
The translator of this work in the 19th century collection of Ante-Nicene Fathers
(vol. IV, p.191) includes the following sentence in his summary preface at the head of chapter 29: "For they believe not only
that he was innocent, but with reason that he was God." Such an idea is nowhere to be found in the text, and the context of
the charge and its response cannot reasonably be said to imply it. Nor do the other things Minucius says which scorn different
aspects of the Christian faith (such as gods being born in the present time or performing miracles) allow us to draw such
an implication. To verse 2 the translator offers this wishful footnote: "A reverent allusion to the Crucified, believed in
and worshiped as God." What one cannot believe is missing, one will read into the text, no matter what.
A more recent commentator, G. W. Clarke (Ancient Christian Writers #39, 1949)
makes this observation in an end note: "A remarkable avoidance of any mention of the Incarnation. Indeed, so anxious is Minucius
Felix to avoid admitting such a difficult doctrine that he gives the appearance of denying it." Indeed he does. And while
Clarke compares this to Arnobius' "coyness" on the same topic, this later (c.300) Christian apologist was in no way reluctant
or dishonest in admitting it, even though he lived at a time of greater persecution. "We worship one who was born a man. What
then? Do you worship no one who was born a man? . . . But he died nailed to the cross. So what? Neither does the kind and
disgrace of the death change his words or deeds." (Against the Heathen, I.37 & 40).
Minucius goes on in this passage to cite the folly of heathen peoples who do
"choose a man for their worship," but he makes no such admissions for Christians. As to the accusation of worshiping crosses,
he says dismissively: "We do not adore them, nor do we wish for them." And he goes on to admonish the pagan for being guilty
of using signs of crosses in their own worship and everyday life. There is not a hint that for Minucius the cross bears any
sacred significance or requires defending in a Christian context.
From this refutation of the calumny of Jesus and his cross, he proceeds ("Next . . .") to challenge those who accuse
Christians of the slaughter of children. There is nothing in the way Minucius has dealt with the supposed heart of the Christian
faith to differentiate it from all these surrounding horrors. The disparaging tone is unredeemed.
One commentator, H. J. Baylis (Minucius Felix, p.148), in addition to expressing
his regret that the writer has been so silent in defending the person of Christ, also laments the fact that he missed a golden
opportunity to refute the charge about licentious feasts and cannabilistic initiation rites by describing the Eucharist. He
could have defended, says Baylis, the sacramental significance and pure conduct of this Christian agape (love feast)
over Jesus' body and blood. Baylis finds it equally "odd" that in speaking of the sources of the "truth about the Godhead"
(38), Minucius is silent on the teachings of Jesus himself, or Jesus' own status as Son within that Godhead.
The survival of this document, with its out-and-out dismissal of the central tenets of Christianity, is perhaps surprising,
but it was no doubt possible only because a certain veiled ambiguity could be read into a verse like 29:2 above, and by letting
this perception override the derogatory tone and jarring silence of the passage and document as a whole. Baylis has labelled
29:2 "oblique," but Minucius' stark language rules out any such escape route. This scholar, too, reads into Minucius' defense
something which is not evidently there: "Yes, we adore one who was crucified, but he is neither a criminal nor a mere man."
Those who are capable of letting historical documents say what they obviously seem to
be saying will recognize that Minucius Felix is a true 'smoking gun' pointing to a Christian denial of the historical
Jesus. Even though this document indicates that there were others within the movement who believed in such a figure, and that
there were historical Jesus traditions circulating, this does not automatically validate the historicity of such a figure,
especially as the author is writing no earlier than the mid-second century. But the key consideration is this: such a denial
as Minucius Felix voices would hardly have been possible within the context of a movement which had actually begun with an
historical Jesus, and so we can say that this document does indeed provide strong evidence of the non-existence of this figure.
To the dispassionate eye, Minucius Felix is one Christian who will have no truck with those, in other circles of his
religion, who profess the worship of a Jesus who was crucified in Judea under the governorship of Pontius Pilate, rumors of which
have reached pagan ears and elicited much scorn and condemnation. To claim that a whole generation of apologists would falsely
convey such an exterior to those they are seeking to win over, that they would deliberately indulge in this kind of Machiavellian
deception, is but one of the desperate measures which modern Christian scholars have been forced to adopt in their efforts
to deal with a Christian record that stubbornly refuses to paint the picture they all want to see.
* *
* *
The apologists were not fools. Their literary and polemical talents were considerable. They were versed in a wide
range of ancient knowledge, in the intricate subtleties of contemporary philosophy. That they could design careful and elaborate
pieces of apologetic writing that yet contained such devastating omissions and weaknesses as we have seen in Minucius Felix,
in Theophilus, in Athenagoras, in Tatian, is not feasible.
If an author like Minucius Felix is being silent for political reasons, why would he
choose to place in the mouth of his pagan spokesperson accusations concerning the very thing he is deliberately silent on?
Why would he allow the opponent such critical and derogatory declarations about the central object of Christian worship when
he has already decided he must deny himself the luxury of answering them? Why would he place in the Christian's own
mouth, as he does in chapters 21 and 23, sweeping and scornful statements which go against elements of the Christian faith
with no possibility of offering saving qualifications? There is not even an attempt, through veiled language and implication,
to assuage the 'knowing' Christian reader, to show that such saving exceptions are present in his own mind. In fact, his treatment
of these faith subjects is tantamount to a denial of them.
At the end of Minucius Felix the writer has his pagan character converted to
Christianity. But what is the use of converting someone like Caecilius to a religion which has had all its essential elements
concealed? When Caecilius arrives "on the morrow" for his first lesson as a catechumen, will Octavius say to him, "Oh, by
the way, there were a few details I left out yesterday." If a Christian is going to appeal to a pagan according to philosophical
and logical principles, how will he then turn around and subsequently present the Christian mysteries and dogmas which he
must be aware go counter to such principles? His own argumentation will then be in danger of being turned against him. And
his dishonesty will place himself and his faith in a dishonorable light.
It must be stressed that nowhere in the literature of the time is there support for the standard scholarly rationalization
about the apologists' silence on the figure of Jesus. Nowhere is it discussed or even intimated that these writers have in
fact deliberately left out the essential elements of Christian faith in their defences of it, for reasons of political correctness
or anything else. The occasionally quoted account of Origen in the third century, that he sometimes expounded his ethical
views without labeling them as Christian, since he feared his listeners' hostility to the very name of Christianity and Christ,
is not applicable here, for in such cases Origen was not identifying himself as a Christian at all, he was not offering a
defence of Christianity, even in a limited way. If he had been, he would certainly not have left himself open to challenges
he was not allowed to answer. His own writings are proof of this. Origen does not conceal Jesus or his resurrection. He counters
every scoff and calumny of Celsus with all the resources at his disposal.
This is true also of Tertullian, writing his apology around the year 200 and borrowing,
or at least using as inspiration, parts of the work of Minucius Felix. Tertullian indulges in no such cryptic concealment.
In his own day, the hostility to Christianity was no easier than it had been a generation earlier when Felix wrote, or a mere
two decades since Athenagoras and Theophilus had penned their defences. Tertullian's work is full of vivid references to Christ's
incarnation, to his death and resurrection. Near the end of his account of "that Christ, the Son of God who appeared among
us," he declares: "let no one think it is otherwise than we have represented, for none may give a false account of his
religion . . . . We say, and before all men we say, and torn and bleeding under your tortures we cry out, 'We worhip
God through Christ!' " Apparently, if we believe the commentators, the bulk of the second century apologists possessed no
such conviction, no such courage. Certainly, Tertullian would have had no sympathy with their policy of concealment. The above
quote may even be a veiled condemnation of them, if he were familiar with the likes of Athenagoras or Tatian or Theophilus.
Or it may have been directed at Minucius Felix himself, whose work he would have felt constrained to expand on and fill in
the painfully missing blanks.
As a final note, we might ask: where are the writers (for we might expect there to be some) who openly
and in unmistakable words reject the figure of Jesus, with no possibility of ambiguity? Until we realize that no such document
would ever have reached us through two millennia of Christian censorship. For probably the same reason, we possess no pagan
writing which discusses the case for rejection of the historical Jesus. Even Celsus (who does not do this) survives only piecemeal
in Origen's great refutation of him. On the other hand, it is likely that even leading pagan thinkers like Celsus would have
had no way to verify or disprove the circulating Christian story and narrative accounts of Jesus of Nazareth, nor would they
have possessed the exegetical tools and abilities to disprove Christian claims through a study of the documents themselves.
In any case, all of these documents, given the poor state of communication and availability of materials in the ancient world,
would hardly have been accessible to someone who might think of undertaking such a task.
|
The theory that Christianity could have begun without an historical
Jesus of Nazareth has been adamantly resisted by New Testament scholarship since it was first put forward some 200 years ago.
It has generally been held by a small minority of investigators, usually "outsiders." An important factor in this imbalance
has been the fact that, traditionally, the great majority working in the field of New Testament research have been religious
apologists, theologians, scholars who are products of divinity schools and university religion departments, not historians
per se. To suggest that a certain amount of negative bias may be operating among that majority where the debate over an historical
Jesus has been concerned, is simply to state the obvious. Nor is such a statement to be considered out of order, especially
in the face of the common 'argument' so often put forward against the mythicist position: that the vast majority of New Testament
scholars have always rejected the proposition of a non-existent Jesus, and continue to do so. In fact, the latter is simply
an "appeal to authority" and cannot by itself be given significant weight.
It is true that such a bias as may exist in traditional ranks does not automatically mean that they are wrong, or
that the mythicist viewpoint is correct. What we need to do is examine the negative position taken by the opposing side and
consider its substance. The problem is, traditional scholarship has offered very little of substance in opposing the theory
that Jesus never existed, and that is especially true in recent times. Even more progressive scholarship, such as the Jesus
Seminar, has never seriously addressed the question (other than an informal opinion poll among the Seminar's members when
it first began its work). Not a single first-rank critical scholar that I am aware of has devoted even an article to it, let
alone a book.
Something like The Evidence for Jesus (1986) by R. T. France, Vice-Principal of the London Bible College, hardly
fills that role, and is devoted to illuminating the figure of an historical Jesus—a largely orthodox one—not just
to defending his existence. As a defense it is quite ineffectual, taking no account (since it largely predates them) of recent
insights into Q, the pervasive midrashic content of Mark, the modeling of Mark's passion story on the traditional tale of
the Suffering Righteous One, and much else that has given ongoing support to the no-Jesus theory. Graham Stanton, in his The
Gospels and Jesus (1989), devotes a chapter to addressing the views of mythicist G. A. Wells. Stanton's 'case' against Wells' position is little
more than a citation of Josephus, Tacitus and Pliny (discussed below)—and an appeal to the authority that comes with
the majority's acceptance "that Jesus existed." Ian Wilson, in Jesus: The Evidence (1984), does much the same, first
acknowledging the uncertainty and contradiction in the early evidence, and then having recourse to the same trio of ancient
'witnesses.' All of them raise points that show little or no understanding for the depth and sophistication of the mythicist
position. J. D. G. Dunn, in his one-page "Note on Professor Wells' View" in The Evidence for Jesus (1985), falls back
on the old timeworn explanations for Paul's silence on a human figure. He, too, asks questions that show he is trapped within
the old paradigm and unable to grasp how standard objections to the mythicist position dissolve, as do many of the longstanding
problems in New Testament research, when the new paradigm of an evolving historical Jesus is applied to the evidence.
In the past fifteen years we have seen the orthodox Christian story systematically dismantled by critical scholarship
like that of the Jesus Seminar, many of whose members have become increasingly secular and scientific in their outlook, something
to be applauded. Insights into the dubious authenticity of Christian traditions, into the derivation of the Gospels and their
antecedents, into the Christian movement as it developed within the context of its time, have been coming with gathering speed,
not to mention radical positions on the historical Jesus that would have been unheard of little more than a decade ago. Within
such circles of modern scholarship one might expect a serious and comprehensive defense against the most threatening position
ever taken against the foundations of Christianity, one that is gaining an ever greater number of supporters and higher profile,
including in several recent books published in both North America and Europe. Yet none has been forthcoming. In the absence of such
a defense, an appeal to the majority viewpoint on the question of Jesus' existence is misplaced.
*
* *
*
The non-Christian witness to Jesus is anything but supportive of his existence. Until almost the end of the first
century, there is not a murmur of him in the Jewish or pagan record. The Alexandrian Jewish philosopher Philo, who lived until
about 50 CE and wrote of unusual sects like the Therapeutae and the Essenes, has nothing to say about Jesus or Christians.
Justus of Tiberias, a Jewish historian who wrote in Galilee in the 80s (his works are now lost), is reported later to have made no mention
whatever of Jesus. Pliny the Elder (died 79 CE) collected data on all manner of natural and astronomical phenomena, even those
which were legendary and which he himself did not necessarily regard as factual, but he records no prodigies associated with
the beliefs of Christians, such as an earthquake or darkening of the skies at a crucifixion, or any star of Bethlehem. The
first Roman satirist to scorn a sect which believed in a crucified Judean founder who had been a god was not Martial at the
end of the first century, nor Juvenal in the first half of the second century, but Lucian in the 160s. Reports of Epictetus,
the great Stoic philosopher of the early second century who preached universal brotherhood to the poor and humble masses,
record no knowledge on his part of a Jewish precursor. Nor does Seneca, the empire's leading ethicist during the reign of
Nero, make reference to such a figure. Other historians of the time, like Plutarch and Quintilian, are equally silent.
The famous passage about Jesus in chapter 18 of Josephus' Antiquities of the Jews (published around 93 CE),
the so-called "Testimonium Flavianum," is widely acknowledged to be, as it stands, a later Christian interpolation. It speaks
naively and devotionally of Jesus and declares him to have been the Messiah. Origen in the third century tells us that Josephus
did not believe in Jesus as the Messiah, a remark likely prompted by the fact that Josephus declared Vespasian the object
of the messianic prophecies (in Jewish War 6.5.4). This remark by Origen shows that the declaration in Antiquities
18 did not exist in his copy. But neither does Origen or anyone else before the 4th century mention any other reference
to Jesus here. Such a silence argues against the fallback claim that even though Christians later amended it, an original
reference to Jesus can be extracted from the present one. This "authentic residue" of the Testimonium would not only have
been positive enough to invite comment by such as Origen, it still contains opinions about Jesus that Josephus is unlikely
to have held. As for the passing identification in Antiquities 20 that "James" was the brother of Jesus known as the
Christ, there are problems in accepting this too as original to Josephus, such as his alleged use of the term "Christ" (Messiah),
a subject which Josephus shows sign of being reluctant to discuss in any of his works. Thus, the Josephan references have
too many problems to constitute reliable support for Jesus' existence. For a thorough examination of both Josephus' passages,
see Supplementary Article No. 10: Josephus Unbound: Reopening the Josephus Question.
The Roman historian Tacitus, in his Annals written around 115, makes the first pagan reference to Jesus as a man executed
in the reign of Tiberius. This is not likely to have been the result of a search of some archive, for the Romans hardly kept
records of the countless crucifixions around the empire going back almost a century. We have no evidence of such extensive
record-keeping. Besides, Tacitus is not known as a thorough researcher, which is illustrated by the fact that he gets Pilate's
title wrong, something that might have been corrected had he consulted an official record. Scholars such as Norman Perrin
(The New Testament: An Introduction, p.407) acknowledge that Tacitus' "information" probably came from local Christian
hearsay and police interrogation; this would have been at a time when the idea of an historical founder had recently taken
hold in Rome. There is even some reason to doubt the authenticity of this passage, despite its vilifying description of Christians.
The association of a persecution of Christians with the great fire in Nero's Rome (the context of Tacitus' reference) is nowhere
mentioned by Christian commentators for the next several centuries.
Pliny the Younger's well-known letter to Trajan, written from Asia Minor around 112 and asking the emperor for advice on
the prosecution of Christians, says nothing about a recent historical man, let alone biographical elements. "Christ," perhaps
a reference to the Jewish Messiah idea, is simply identified as a god in Christian worship. And the historian Suetonius' reference
(around 120) to "Chrestus" as someone, or some idea, that has produced agitation among Jews in Rome, is so flimsy and uncertain,
no secure meaning can be drawn from it, much less a connection to Christianity and an historical Jesus. It could be referring
to Jewish messianic expectation or to an early belief in a divine Christ.
There are those who appeal to obscure references in the historians Thallus and Phlegon about eclipses of the sun allegedly
associated with the crucifixion, but such pagan writers, their works now lost, come to us only through Christian commentators.
The latter could well have put their own spin on reports which originally had nothing to do with a Jesus, but simply referred
to an eclipse of the sun which astronomers date in the year 29. Certainly, there are no other reports at the time among either
Mediterranean writers or others around the world about a universal darkness at midday.
As for the references to Jesus in the Jewish Talmud: even though some remarks are attributed to rabbis who flourished
around the end of the first century (none earlier), they were not written down before the third century and later. Such records
cannot be relied upon to preserve authentic traditions of a few centuries earlier, ones that may have been influenced by,
or created in response to, Christian claims of the second century and later. In any case, such references are often so cryptic
and off the mark they can scarcely be identified with the Gospel figure. Some have him dying by stoning or hanging, rather
than by crucifixion. One places Jesus in the time of the Maccabean king Alexander Jannaeus around 100 BCE; another identifies the
husband of Jesus' mother as someone who is said to have been a contemporary of rabbi Akiba in the second century CE. All of
them allot responsibility for the death of this figure solely to the Jews, a strange situation in Jewish rabbinic tradition
if the Gospel story were history and widely known. As a witness to an historical Jesus, the Talmudic references are worthless.
*
* *
*
There are a number of fundamental problems in mainstream New Testament research that can be dealt with under the heading
of "Five Fallacies" which that research has traditionally been guilty of. (I will assume the reader's familiarity with Parts
One to Three.) The First Fallacy is the idea that Jews, both in Palestine and across the empire, could have come to
believe—or been converted to the idea by others— that a human man was the Son of God. Within a handful of years
of Jesus' supposed death we know of Christian communities all over the eastern Mediterranean, many of them involving at least
some Jewish adherents. Such Christians may have been numerous and troublesome enough in Rome to be expelled by Claudius
as early as the 40s. At the very least, Paul in Romans speaks of a congregation of the Christ that has been established in
the capital of the empire "for many years" (15:23). Traditional Christian views have maintained that such communities
were the product of dusty disciples from Judea who went off to centers big and small and almost overnight managed to convince
great numbers of Jews (as well as gentiles) that a humble preacher they had never seen or heard of, executed in Jerusalem
as a subversive, had risen from the dead, redeemed the world, and was in fact God's pre-existent Son who had helped him create
the universe. This is an incredible proposition.
I said in Part One that Judaism's fundamental theological tenet was: God is one. It is true that the first Jewish
Christians, such as Paul, were flirting with a compromise to monotheism in postulating a divine Son in heaven, even though
he was entirely spiritual in nature and was conceived of as a part of God; this Son was derived from scripture and was an
expression of the prominent philosophical idea of the age that the ultimate Deity gave off emanations of himself which served
as intermediaries with the world. But this is a far cry from turning a recent man who had walked the sands of Palestine into part of the Godhead.
(It was essentially gentiles who were later to create such an idea, and it produced the "parting of the ways" between the
Christian movement and its Jewish roots.) Almost any Jew would have reacted with apoplexy to the unprecedented message that
a man was God. In a society in which the utter separation of the divine from the human was an obsession, the Jewish God could
not be represented by even the suggestion of a human form, and thousands bared their necks before the swords of Pilate simply
to protest against the human images on Roman standards being brought into the city to overlook the Temple. To believe that
ordinary Jews were willing to bestow on any human man, no matter how impressive, all the titles of divinity and full identification
with the ancient God of Abraham is simply inconceivable.
Paul is not only assumed to have done this, but he did so without ever telling us that anyone challenged him on it,
that he had to defend such a blasphemous proposition. His comment in 1 Corinthians 1:23 that the cross of Christ is a "scandal"
refers to his idea that the divine Messiah had been crucified (a spiritual figure in a mythical setting), not that a recent
man was God.
The Second Fallacy is an extension of the first, and I touched on it in Part Three. Scholars are faced with a bewildering
variety of expression in earliest Christianity. Many circles of belief lacked fundamental Christian doctrines, and different
aspects of Jesus are said to have been preserved by separate groups. Modern critical scholarship has put forward a curious
scenario to explain all this. Various groups who came in contact with Jesus or the missionary movement about him are supposed
to have focused on different aspects of him, some exclusively on the teachings, others on the miracles, still others on the
message about his death and perceived resurrection as a redeeming act. Some came up with unique interpretations of him. Some
of these groups saw him in entirely human terms, while others, like Paul, turned him into God and abandoned all interest in
his pre-resurrection earthly life and identity. Burton Mack (in A Myth of Innocence, p.98f) suggests that this cultic
deification of Jesus took place under the influence of gentiles in Hellenistic circles like Antioch. But this hardly explains
Paul, allegedly a Jew born and bred, who was converted within two to five years of Jesus' supposed death. Did a whole Hellenistic
mythology develop around Jesus almost overnight, in the heart of Jerusalem—and Paul accepted it? Or did he not
believe in Jesus as the Son of God right from the start? Perhaps we are to view the theology of Paul's letters, our earliest
record written two decades later, as a result of the insidious influence of gentiles at Antioch.
Such scenarios fail to provide any convincing explanation for why such an immediate fragmentation would have taken
place, why the Christian movement began as "fluid and amorphous" (James Robinson in Trajectories Through Early Christianity,
p.114f). Mack admits that "much of the evidence is secondhand, and all of it is later." Out of a record of multiplicity, Christian
scholars have deduced a single founder and point of origin which is based on a later stage: the Gospel story, formed by the
postulated reconvergence of the original diverging strands. But no document records this initial phenomenon of differing "responses"
to the historical man, this break-up of Jesus into his component parts. Given a record whose earliest manifestation is nothing
but diversity, common sense requires us to assume the likelihood that this was in fact the incipient state, and that the new
faith arose in many different places with many different expressions. Some elements, such as the teachings, would have had
no connection to a Jesus in their early stages. Most of this diversity was later to be drawn together and recast under a composite
new figure, courtesy of the evangelists.
The above type of scenario involves a Third Fallacy. Scholars have long asked questions like that of Elizabeth Schlüsser-Fiorenza
("Wisdom Mythology and the Christological Hymns of the New Testament" in Aspects of Wisdom in Judaism and Early Christianity,
p.34): "Why do the hymns use the language of myth to speak of Jesus of Nazareth who was not a mythic figure but a concrete
historical person?" I pointed out in Part One that the very earliest expression about Jesus we find in the Christian record
presents him solely as a cosmic figure, the pre-existent creator and sustainer of the universe (Paul and his school), a heavenly
High Priest and Platonic Logos-type entity (Epistle to the Hebrews), a descending redeemer in the spiritual realm (the pre-Pauline
hymns), and so on. All such presentations of Jesus are said to be ways various circles adopted of "interpreting" the man Jesus
of Nazareth—according to sacred scripture and current philosophical and mythical concepts. But it would help if any
of these early writers gave us even a hint that such an intention was anywhere in their minds. How are we to understand an
"interpretation" when the thing supposedly being interpreted is never mentioned? John Knox (Myth and Truth, p.59) points
to Ephesians 1:3–10 as a kind of mythological drama created to explain Jesus, entirely in supernatural terms. Knox speaks
of "the remembered man Jesus" and "the wonder of his deeds and words." But where are these things in Ephesians 1:3–10,
or anywhere else? He says that the myth has been created based on memories of the Lord, but where are those memories? We cannot
accept Knox's claim that the myth in Ephesians is built upon "historical data" when that data is never pointed at or even
alluded to. A better explanation would be that the historical data has been added to the myth at a later time. The whole concept
that early Christian writers are "interpreting" Jesus of Nazareth even when they never mention him is a blatant "reading into"
the text on the part of those who must see the presumed historical figure behind all this scriptural and mythological presentation.
Scholars, in seeking an explanation for Paul's blanket silence on the historical Jesus, have given us a Fourth Fallacy.
They rationalize that Paul "had no interest" in Jesus' earthly incarnation, that his theology did not require it. This is
difficult to fathom. Paul's faith is centered on the crucifixion. What bizarre mental processes could have led him to disembody
it, to completely detach it from its historical time and place, from the life which culminated on Calvary? Why would he transplant
the great redeeming act to some mythological realm of demonic powers who were responsible for "crucifying the Lord of glory"
(1 Corinthians 2:8)? Why would he give Christ "significance only as a transcendent divine being" (Herman Ridderbos, Paul
and Jesus, p.3)?
And what of the details of Jesus' life? Could Pilate not have served Paul as an example of the "wisdom of the world"
which could not understand the "wisdom of God"? For Paul, baptism is the prime sacrament of Christian ritual; through it believers
receive the Spirit and are adopted as sons of God. Yet we are to assume that Paul, in presenting his baptismal rite (such
as in Romans 6), cared nothing about Jesus' own baptism by John, about such traditions that he had received the Spirit in
the form of a dove, that he had been adopted as Son by the Father in the voice from heaven. We are to assume that in all the
bitter debates he engaged in through his letters, such as on the validity of the Jewish dietary laws, Paul never felt a need
to introduce the Lord's own actions and teachings concerning the subjects under dispute. Are we to accept, too, that Jesus'
earthly signs and wonders would not have been an incalculable selling point to gentiles, immersed as they were in popular
pagan traditions of the wonder-working "divine man," a concept which fitted the earthly career of Jesus to a "T"? And are
we to believe that, even if Paul had expunged Christ's human life from his own mind, his audiences and converts likewise felt
no interest and did not press him for details of Jesus' earthly sayings and deeds—something of which he shows no sign
in his letters? In any event, explanations for Paul's silence and lack of interest would have to apply to all the other early
epistle writers, who are equally silent—a situation so extraordinary as to defy rationalization. Amid such considerations,
the argument from silence becomes legitimate and compelling.
Finally, many today find increasingly acceptable the direction which most recent liberal scholarship seems to be following:
that Jesus was only a man, a Jewish preacher who was somehow divinized after his death, a death which did not result in resurrection.
But here it seems that they face an insurmountable dilemma, a Fifth Fallacy. First of all, such a divinization on the scale
that Jesus underwent would have been unprecedented, and there is no more unlikely milieu for this to have happened in than
a Jewish one. Nor is this divinization gradual, a graph line which ascends as his reputation grows, as the things he did in
his life took on magnified stature and interpretation. Rather, at the earliest we can see any evidence for it, Jesus is already
at the highest point, cast in an entirely mythological picture: fully divine, pre-existent before the creation of the world,
moving in the celestial spheres and grappling with the demonic forces. Those deeds of his life which should have contributed
to such an elevation are nowhere in evidence.
Let's put the dilemma this way: If this man Jesus had had the explosive effect on his followers that is said of him,
and on the thousands of believers who responded so readily to the message about him, such a man would have had to blaze in
the firmament of his time. That impact would have been based on the force of his personality, on the unique things he said
and did. There is no other way.
And yet the picture we see immediately after Jesus' death, and for the next two generations in every extant document,
flatly contradicts this. The blazing star immediately drops out of sight. No contemporary historian, philosopher or popular
writer records him. There is no sign of any tradition or phenomenon associated with him. For over half a century Christian
writers themselves totally ignore his life and ministry. Not a saying is quoted and attributed to him. Not a miracle is marveled
at. No aspect of his human personality, anchored within any biographical setting, is ever referred to. The details of his
life, the places of his career: they raise no interest in any of his believers. This is an eclipse that does not even grant
us a trace of a corona!
If, on the other hand, Jesus was simply an ordinary human man, a humble (if somewhat charismatic) Jewish preacher,
who really said little of what has been imputed to him, who performed no real miracles, and who of course did not rise from
the dead—all of which might explain why he attracted no great attention and could have his life ignored as unimportant
by his later followers—what, then, is the explanation for how such a life and personality could have given rise to the
vast range of response the scholars postulate, to the cosmic theology about him, to the conviction that he had risen from
the dead, to the unstoppable movement which early Christianity seems to have been? This is an unsolvable dilemma.
If all we have in the earliest Christian record is this cosmic divine figure who moves in mythological spheres—just
like all the other savior deities of the day—are we not compelled by scientific principles to accept that this and no
more was the object of early Christian worship? If, to support this, we can present within the evidence a logical process
by which such a figure can be seen to take on a biography and a place in history, do we have any justification for continuing
to maintain that the divine, cosmic Christ grew out of the human Jesus of Nazareth?
*
* *
*
"As a historian I do not know for certain
that Jesus really existed, that he is anything more than the figment of some overactive imaginations....In my view, there
is nothing about Jesus of Nazareth that we can know beyond any possible doubt. In the mortal life we have there are only probabilities.
And the Jesus that scholars have isolated in the ancient gospels, gospels that are bloated with the will to believe, may turn
out to be only another image that merely reflects our deepest longings." Robert W. Funk, Jesus Seminar Founder and Co-Chair.
(From The Fourth R, January-February 1995.)
THE SECOND CENTURY APOLOGISTS
The Christian Apologists of the second century present us with a dramatic picture of continuing diversity in the Christian
movement and, among most of them, a surprising and revealing silence on Jesus of Nazareth.
The first 100 years of Christianity have received the greatest attention from Christian scholarship. Within the period
up to about 130, so conventional wisdom has it, lie Jesus himself and the origins of the church, as well as all the documents
which ended up in the canon of the New Testament. Also included are the surviving writings by that varied group known as the
Apostolic Fathers, which reveal some of the internal conditions and conflicts within the growing movement. The period following,
and running for another 100 years or so, was the age of the Apologists. These were men like Justin Martyr who presented and
justified Christianity to an outside world which was largely hostile to the new faith.
In Parts One to Three of the Main Articles, I provided a picture of the origins and growth of Christianity which rejects
the existence of an historical Jesus of Nazareth. One of the key features of that picture is the unusual diversity of expression
to be found in the early Christian record: about the figure of Jesus, about Christian theology, ritual practice and views
of salvation. This diversity points not to a human founder and single missionary movement proceeding out of him, but to a
widespread and uncoordinated religious movement founded on various beliefs in a divine, intermediary Son of God, a wholly
spiritual entity. A related feature is the virtually universal silence in that early record on anything to do with the human
man and events known to us from the Gospels.
What do we find as Christianity enters its second 100 years? In fact, we find more of the same. Those who have studied
the apologists have tended to make some surprising observations. They note how little continuity these writers show with earlier
traditions. Their ideas often have nothing in common with those of the New Testament epistles and even the Gospels. There
is no dependence on Paul. Moreover, such writers seem not to move in ecclesiastical circles. Even Justin, though he worked
in Rome, has nothing to say about bishops and church organizations. And almost all of them before the year 180 (Justin being
the major exception) are silent on the Gospels and the figure of Jesus contained in them. In fact, one could say that they
pointedly ignore any historical figure at all.
This astonishing state of affairs, taken with the fact that the Gospels and the Acts of the Apostles show no sign
of surfacing in any other Christian writers until the middle of the second century, supports the conclusion that the figure
of Jesus of Nazareth was a development in Christian thought which came to life only in the Gospels and gradually, throughout
the course of the second century, imposed itself on the movement as a whole.
Let's take a closer look at the evidence supplied by the Christian apologists.
Scholars specializing in the second century have characterized the Christianity of the apologists as essentially a
philosophical movement. Whereas the premier expression of Christian development in the first century, the one centered around
Paul and his circles, was an apocalyptically oriented phenomenon with a strong Jewish flavor and preaching a dying savior,
that of the apologists, who were all located in cosmopolitan centers across much of the empire, was grounded in Platonic philosophy
and Hellenistic Judaism.
Justin, the apologist about whom we know the most, came to Christianity after having investigated all the other popular
philosophies of his day: the Stoics, Peripatetics (based on Aristotle), the Pythagoreans. Finally, he was schooled in Middle
Platonism, the predominant philosophical outlook of the era which colored everything else, especially in its strongly religious
concerns about the nature of the Deity and its relation to humanity. When Justin encountered Christianity, he judged it the
best version of contemporary philosophy. In Rome, he seems to have had no connection with any ecclesiastical
body, but set up his own school, teaching Christian philosophy in the manner of pagan philosophers of the time.
And what was this 'Christian philosophy' as presented by the apologists as a group? There is no question that it had
roots in Jewish ideas. It preached the monotheistic worship of the Jewish God, a God touted as superior to those of the pagans.
For information about this God it looked to the Hebrew scriptures. It placed great value on a mode of life founded on Jewish
ethics; again, something touted as superior to the ethical philosophy of the pagans. At the same time, it derived from Platonism
the concept of a Son of God, a 'second God' or Logos (Word), a force active in the world and serving as an intermediary between
God and humanity. This idea of the Logos was floating in the air of most Greek philosophies and even Hellenistic Judaism.
Thus the religion of the apologists has been styled "Platonic-biblical" or "religious Platonism with a Judaistic cast."
It would seem to have grown out of Jewish Diaspora circles which had immersed themselves in Greek philosophy. (Justin and
others, including the movement known as Gnosticism, provide evidence of heretical Jewish sects, with many gentiles attached,
which had evolved a great distance from traditional Jewish thinking.) There is little to suggest that this religion proceeded
out of the first century branch of Christian development surrounding Paul. There is none of Paul's or the Gospels' focus on
the Messiah/Christ or the end of the world, and the apologists' views of salvation are rooted in Greek mysticism, not Jewish
martyrology for sin. Instead, the two expressions seem like separate branches of a very broad tree.
Justin, and whoever recast the Gospel of John to include the Prologue, with its hymn equating the Logos with Jesus,
came to believe that the intermediary Word, the spiritual Son of God, had been incarnated in a human figure as recounted in
the Gospels. But is this true of the apologists as a whole? The amazing fact is, that of the five or six major apologists
up to the year 180 (after that, Irenaeus, Tertullian, Clement of Alexandria and Origen are all firmly anchored in Gospel tradition),
none, with the exception of Justin, introduces an historical Jesus into their defences of Christianity to the pagans.
Consider Theophilus of Antioch. According to Eusebius, he became bishop of the Christian community
in that city in 168, but one has to wonder. In his treatise To Autolycus, apparently written toward the year 180, he
tells us that he was born a pagan and became a Christian after reading the Jewish scriptures, a situation common to virtually
all the apologists.
But what, for Theophilus, is the meaning of the name "Christian"? The Autolycus of the title has asked him this question.
He answers (I.12): "Because we are anointed with the oil of God." (The name "Christ" itself means Anointed One, from the anointed
kings of Israel.) In fact, Theophilus never mentions Christ, or Jesus, at all! He makes no
reference to a founder-teacher; instead, Christians have their doctrines and knowledge of God through the Holy Spirit. Along
with the pronouncements of the Old Testament prophets, he includes "the gospels" (III.12), but these too are the inspired word
of God, not a record of Jesus' words and deeds. When he quotes ethical maxims corresponding to Jesus' Gospel teachings, he
presents them (II.14) as the teaching of these gospels, not of Jesus himself.
And what is Theophilus' Son of God? He is the Word through whom God created the world, who was begat by him along
with Wisdom (II.10). He is the governing principle and Lord of all creation, inspiring the prophets and the world in general
to a knowledge of God. Yet Theophilus has not a thing to say about this Word's incarnation into flesh, or any deed performed
by him on earth. In fact, he hastens to say (II.22) that this is not a Son in the sense of begetting, but as innate in the
heart of God. Here he seems to quote part of the opening lines of the Gospel of John, the Word as God and instrumental in
creation, but nothing else. Is this from the full-blown Gospel, or perhaps from the Logos hymn John drew upon? (The name "John",
the only evangelist mentioned, could be a later marginal gloss inserted into the text; but see below.) Such writers, Theophilus
says, are inspired men, not witnesses to an historical Jesus.
As for redemption, all will gain eternal life who are obedient to the commandments of God (II.27). There is no concept
in Theophilus of an atoning sacrificial death of Jesus, a death he never mentions. And when challenged on his doctrine that
the dead will be raised (Autolycus has demanded: "Show me even one who has been raised from the dead!"), this Christian has
not a word to say about Jesus' own resurrection. He even accuses the pagans of worshiping "dead men" (I.9) and ridicules them
for believing that Hercules and Aesclepius were raised from the dead (I.13). All this, in answer to an Autolycus who has asked:
"Show me thy God."
Athenagoras of Athens, who worked in Alexandria, wrote around the same time, though one ancient witness
places him a few decades earlier. He was a philosopher who had embraced Christianity, but he shows no involvement in any church,
or interest in rituals and sacraments. In A Plea For the Christians addressed to the emperor, he says this of his new
beliefs (10): "We acknowledge one God . . . by whom the Universe has been created through his Logos, and set in order and
kept in being . . . for we acknowledge also a Son of God . . . If it occurs to you to enquire what is meant by the Son,
I will state that he is the first product of the Father (who) had the Logos in himself. He came forth to be the idea and energizing
power of all material things."
Unfortunately, in the course of 37 chapters, Athenagoras neglects to tell the emperor that Christians believe this
Logos to have been incarnated in the person of Jesus of Nazareth. He dissects contemporary Platonic and Stoic philosophy,
angels and demons, as well as details of various Greek myths, but he offers not a scrap about the life of the Savior. He presents
(11) Christian doctrine as things "not from a human source, but uttered and taught by God," and proceeds to quote ethical
maxims very close to parts of the Sermon on the Mount: "Love your enemies; bless them that curse you . . . ." Other quotations
he labels as coming from scripture, or from "our teaching." Are these ethical collections that are unattributed to Jesus?
Athenagoras never uses the term "gospel"; he speaks of "the witness to God and the things of God" and enumerates the prophets
and other men, yet he ignores what should have been the greatest witness of them all, Jesus of Nazareth.
With no incarnation, there is in Athenagoras' presentation of the Christian faith no death and resurrection of Jesus,
no sacrifice and Atonement. Eternal life is gained "by this one thing alone: that (we) know God and his Logos" (12). In fact,
the names Jesus and Christ never appear in Athenagoras. Yet he can say (11), "If I go minutely into the particulars of our
doctrines, let it not surprise you." One might be forgiven for regarding this as blatant dishonesty.
The anonymous Epistle to Diognetus is often included with the Apostolic Fathers. But it is really an apology,
a defence of Christianity addressed probably to an emperor, either Hadrian or Marcus Aurelius. Most scholars lean to the earlier
date (c.130). The writer goes so far as to say that the ultimate God sent the Logos, his Son, down to earth, but no time,
place, or identity for this incarnation are provided. The name Jesus never appears. The Son revealed God, but is not portrayed
as a human teacher.
We find an allusion (9) to the Atonement: "He (God) took our sins upon himself and gave his own Son as a ransom for
us," but his description of this act is based on scripture. No Gospel details are mentioned, no manner of the Son's death
(if that's what it was), no resurrection. All this is in response to Diognetus' "close and careful inquiries" about the Christian
religion. (The final two chapters of the sole surviving manuscript, which contain a reference to apostles and disciples of
the Word, have been identified as belonging to a separate document, probably a homily from the mid to late second century.)
We turn now to Tatian, a pupil of Justin. He was converted to Christianity, he says, by reading the Jewish scriptures.
At a later stage of his career, after apostatizing to the heretical sect of the Encratites and going off to Syria, Tatian composed the Diatessaron,
the first known harmony of the four canonical Gospels. But while still in Rome, sometime around 160, he wrote an Apology
to the Greeks, urging pagan readers to turn to the truth. In this description of Christian truth, Tatian uses neither
"Jesus" nor "Christ" nor even the name "Christian." Much space is devoted to outlining the Logos, the creative power of the
universe, first-begotten of the Father, through whom the world was made—but none to the incarnation of this Logos. His
musings on God and the Logos, rather than being allusions to the Gospel of John, as some claim, contradict the Johannine Prologue
in some respects and may reflect Logos commonplaces of the time. Resurrection of the dead is not supported by Jesus' resurrection.
Eternal life is gained through knowledge of God (13:1), not by any atoning sacrifice of Jesus.
In Tatian's Apology we find a few allusions to Gospel sayings, but no specific reference to written Gospels
and no attribution of such things to Jesus. Instead, all knowledge comes from God himself. Tatian says he was "God-taught"
(29:2). He does, however, make a revealing comment about mythical stories, which I will return to in a moment. Finally, around
the year 155, the first Latin apologist, Minucius Felix, wrote a dialogue between a Christian and a heathen, entitled Octavius.
It too presents a Christianity without an historical Jesus, and in fact contains some startling features in this regard. I
will examine it in some detail in the latter part of this article.
*
* *
*
Something extremely odd is going on here. If one leaves aside Justin, there is a silence in the second century apologists
on the subject of the historical Jesus which is almost the equal to that in the first century letter writers. Commentators
on these works, like those studying the earlier epistles, have scrambled to come up with explanations.
One is that the apologists were concerned first and foremost with preaching the monotheistic Father, the God of the
Jews, while debunking the Greek myths with their all-too-human and morally uninspiring divinities. This is true. But it should
not preclude them from devoting some space to the most essential feature of the faith, and besides, the apologists have no
reluctance about bringing in the Son of God in the form of the Logos. In fact, the apologists as a group profess a faith which
is nothing so much as a Logos religion. It is in essence Platonism carried to its fullest religious implications and wedded
with Jewish theology and ethics. The figure of Jesus of Nazareth as the incarnation of the Logos is a graft, an adoption which
was embraced only by Justin.
Of course, the glaring anomaly which must be explained is this: how can an apologist be giving his pagan readers a
meaningful picture of the Christian faith when he leaves out the most central of its elements, the figure of Jesus and what
he had done for salvation? How was the reader to understand the history and origins of the movement without him?
Inevitably, commentators have been led to conclude that the omission—indeed, the suppression—of Jesus
was deliberate. Pagan philosophers like Galen had challenged Christian thinkers that their faith was based on revelation rather
than reasoned philosophical argument. They had ridiculed the idea of a crucified god. The heathen attitude had made it impolitic
to speak of Jesus of Nazareth, and so he needed to be kept in the closet.
Too many common sense arguments tell against this 'explanation.' First, a writer like Athenagoras is quite adept at
reasoned, sophisticated argument. Why not apply such talents to a justification of Christianity's principal tenet? If the
world at large is maligning Jesus, surely the overriding need is to rehabilitate him, not hide him away. Second, this suppression
of Jesus, the misrepresentation of everything from the name "Christian" to the source of Christian ethics, amounts to nothing
less than a denial of Christ. The apologist is constructing a picture which excludes the central elements of the faith,
falsifying his presentation, leaving no room for Jesus. He has gone beyond silence in stating, "I have said all there is to
say." In an age when Christian pride and fortitude required that any penalty be faced—even the ultimate one—rather
than renounce the faith, this gutting of Christian doctrine would have smacked of betrayal. It would have horrified believers
and quickly discredited the apologists in Christian eyes. Could any of them really have chosen to defend the Name by expunging
it?
And who would they be fooling? Any pagan who knew the first thing about Christianity would surely be familiar with
the figure of Jesus of Nazareth as the movement's founder. An 'apology' for the faith which left him out would readily be
seen for the sham that it was, thus foiling the whole object of the exercise. Besides, Justin, the most prominent of the apologists,
felt no such qualms about placing Jesus at the center of his exposition. Tatian was someone who cared not a fig for the objections
or sensibilities of any pagan. And beyond the year 180 no Christian writer felt any need or pressure to suppress Jesus.
Another important consideration is that the apologists are touting the superiority of Christian ethics and its monotheistic
view of God. If Jesus had been the source of these teachings, their stature would have been raised by being presented as the
product of a great teacher; while at the same time, the attribution to Jesus of this estimable body of ethics and theology
would have gone a long way toward redeeming him in pagan eyes for whatever else Christians might have been claiming about
him. The fact that no one but Justin has incorporated the teaching, human Jesus into his appeals to the pagan is too bizarre
a situation. No, some other explanation for the silence of the bulk of the apologetic movement must be sought.
A clue to the solution of this puzzle lies in Tatian's Apology. In chapter 21 he says, "We are not fools, men
of Greece, when we declare that God has been born in the form of man (his only allusion to the incarnation)
. . . Compare your own stories with our narratives." He goes on to describe some of the Greek myths about gods come to earth,
undergoing suffering and even death for the benefaction of mankind. "Take a look at your own records and accept us merely
on the grounds that we too tell stories."
This may well be a reference to the Christian Gospels. But if he can allude to the incarnation in this way, why does
he not deal with it openly and at length? His comment is hardly a ringing endorsement, or a declaration that such stories
are to be accepted as history. The way Tatian compares them to the Greek myths implies that he regards them as being on the
same level. Certainly, he does not rush to point out that the Christian stories are superior or, unlike the Greek ones, factually
true. Nor can we get around the fact that Tatian pointedly ignores those Gospel stories in the rest of his Apology.
(He was to change his mind by the time he composed the Diatessaron.) Furthermore, he ignores them even though his language
clearly implies that the pagans were familiar with them.
There seems to be only one way to interpret all this. We can assume that the philosopher-apologists were familiar
with the Gospel story and its figure of Jesus of Nazareth. But, with the exception of Justin, they have chosen not to integrate
these elements into their own faith, not to identify this reputed historical founder-teacher with their divine Logos and Son
of God, not to regard him as the source of Christian teachings.
This is possible only if the Logos religion the apologists subscribed to, especially at the time of their conversion,
was lacking the figure of Jesus of Nazareth. Only if they could view the Gospel story and its central character as a recent
graft, a fictional tale like those of the Greeks, was it possible for them to reject it, to feel that they could be presenting
the Christian faith legitimately. Only if they felt it were possible for pagans to accept the story of Jesus as a myth like
their own religious myths, was it acceptable for the apologists to present to them a Christianity which ignored or rejected
the figure of Jesus.
As a mix of Platonism and Hellenistic Judaism, the apologists' branch of Christianity had become prominent throughout
the empire in the second century. (Paulinism had gone into eclipse until the ascendancy of the church of Rome and its rehabilitation
of Paul as the latter half of the century progressed.) As we have seen, this Platonic Christianity defined itself in ways
which had nothing to do with an historical Jesus. Nor is it likely to have grown out of Paulinism, as they have virtually
nothing in common.
If development had been as the scholars like to present it, a shift in emphasis from the 'Palestinian' style of Christianity
to one based on Greek philosophy and Hellenistic Judaism, the figure of Jesus would hardly have been dropped; he would have
been integrated into the Platonic picture. This is not a Christian 'utilization' of Greek philosophy. The apologists' faith
is the religious Platonism of the time brought into a Jewish theological and ethical setting (which rendered the Logos
and the faith "anointed" or Christian). It is significant that none of them (possibly excepting Theophilus) have connections
with a church.
Such a picture supports the view that Christianity, for its first 150 years, was a mosaic of uncoordinated expressions.
It was a variegated organism which took root and flowered across the landscape of the empire, a widely divergent mix of Jewish
and Greek features. As time went on, the distillation of Jesus of Nazareth out of certain pores in this organism spread inexorably
across its entire surface, until by the year 200 he was firmly entrenched in every aspect of the faith.
Even Justin gives evidence of this picture. After reaching Rome in the 140s, he encountered some of the
Gospels and embraced the historical man-god they told of. In his apologetic writings, penned in the 150s, Jesus and the Gospels
occupy center stage. For Justin, the Word/Logos "took shape, became man, and was called Jesus Christ" (Apology, 5).
But he has left us an inadvertent record of the nature of the faith he joined before his encounter with the story of a human
Jesus.
The Dialogue with the Jew Trypho was written after the Apology, and the latter can be dated to the early
150s. But the action of Trypho is set at the time of the Second Jewish Revolt, in the 130s, and scholars are confident
that this represents the time of Justin's conversion, which he describes in the opening chapters.
By the sea near Ephesus Justin encounters an old man, a Christian philosopher. After a discussion of the joys and
benefits of philosophy, the old man tells of ancient Jewish prophets who spoke by the Divine Spirit. These prophets, he says,
had proclaimed the glory of God the Father and his Son, the Christ. (This was the interpretation of the Hebrew Bible in Platonic
terms.) Wisdom could come only to those who have it imparted to them by God and his Christ.
At this, says Justin (8:1), "a flame was kindled in my soul; and a love of the prophets and of those who are friends
of Christ possessed me." Justin does not even say (despite the best attempts of some commentators) that he felt a love for
Christ himself, for in the Christianity to which he was converted, Christ was a philosophical concept. He was a part of the
Godhead in heaven, a Logos-type entity. This Christ is a Savior by virtue of the wisdom he imparts (8:2). This is Justin's
concept of salvation here, for he goes on to conclude the story of his conversion by saying to Trypho: "If you are eagerly
looking for salvation, and if you believe in God, you may become acquainted with the Christ of God and, after being initiated,
live a happy life." (Later, under the influence of the Gospels, Justin laid increasing emphasis on the redeeming value of
Christ's death and resurrection, but in the basic Logos religion the Son saves by revealing God.)
Where is Jesus of Nazareth in all this? The old philosopher had not a word to say about him, nor about any incarnation
of the Son. We are fortunate that Justin did not recast the memory of his conversion experience in the light of his later
beliefs based on the Gospels. In those opening chapters of the Dialogue with the Jew Trypho we can see that all the
apologists came to the same Christian faith: a Platonic religious philosophy grounded in Hellenistic Judaism which fails to
include any historical Jesus.
Trypho himself may be a literary invention, but Justin puts into his mouth (8:6) a telling accusation, one which must
have represented a common opinion of the time: "But Christ—if he has indeed been born, and exists anywhere—is
unknown . . . And you, having accepted a groundless report, invent a Christ for yourselves . . . " Trypho also expresses the
opinion that the incarnation is incredible and even Justin admits (Apology, 13) that "sober-minded men" are of the
opinion that "Christians are mad to give a crucified man second place to God." As we shall see, even some Christians were
in agreement.
In passing, I will mention that perhaps the earliest surviving apology, that of Aristides to the emperor Antoninus
Pius, a short and minor work written in Syriac around 140, is clearly dependent on some Gospel account. It speaks of God born
of a virgin, having twelve disciples, pierced died and buried, then rising after three days. This apology comes from a different
milieu, one located in the Palestine-Syria area (where the Synoptic Gospels were written), for it has nothing to say about
the Logos or Greek philosophical concepts.
*
* *
*
I have left until last the most fascinating of all the apologies, a document which could well be called a 'smoking
gun.' The little treatise Octavius was written in Rome, or possibly North Africa, in Latin. It takes the form of a debate
between Caecilius, a pagan, and Octavius, a Christian, chaired and narrated by the author, Minucius Felix, by whose name the
work is now usually referred to.
There has been a long and seesaw debate as to when Minucius Felix was written. A clear literary relationship
exists with Tertullian's much longer Apology, written around the year 200. But who borrowed from whom? A good general
rule says that the later writer tends to expand on what the earlier writer wrote, not chop drastically, especially since in
this case it would mean that Minucius Felix had cut out many important Christian dogmas and every single reference to the
Gospel Jesus—and this, well into the third century, when no one else had any qualms about speaking of such things. This
and other arguments considered, the earlier dating between 150 and 160 is much preferable. (See H. J. Baylis, Minucius
Felix [1928], p.273.)
In this debate, the names of Christ and Jesus are never used, though the word "Christian" appears throughout. Nor
is there any allusion to the Son or Logos. Octavius' Christianity revolves around the Unity and Providence of God and the
rejection of all pagan deities, the resurrection of the body and its future reward or punishment. In regard to the latter,
no appeal is made to Jesus' own resurrection as proof of God's ability and intention to resurrect the dead. Not even in answer
to the challenge (11): "What single individual has returned from the dead, that we might believe it for an example?" Much
of Octavius' argument is devoted to countering the calumnies against Christians which Caecilius, representing general pagan
opinion, enumerates: everything from debauchery to the devouring of infants, to Christian secrecy and hopes for the world's
fiery destruction.
But here is where it gets interesting. For no other apologist but Justin has voiced and dealt with one particular
accusation which the writer puts into the mouth of Caecilius. The list of calumnies in chapter 9 runs like this (partly paraphrased):
"This abominable congregation should be
rooted out . . . a religion of lust and fornication. They reverence the head of an ass . . . even the genitals of their priests
. . . . And some say that the objects of their worship include a man who suffered death as a criminal, as well as the wretched
wood of his cross; these are fitting altars for such depraved people, and they worship what they deserve . . . . Also,
during initiations they slay and dismember an infant and drink its blood . . . at their ritual feasts they indulge in shameless
copulation."
Remember that a Christian is composing this passage. (The sentence in italics is translated in full.) He has included
the central element and figure of the Christian faith, the person and crucifixion of Jesus, within a litany of ridiculous
and unspeakable calumnies leveled against his religion—with no indication, by his language or tone, that this reference
to a crucified man is to be regarded as in any way different from the rest of the items: disreputable accusations which need
to be refuted. Could a Christian author who believed in a crucified Jesus and his divinity really have been capable of this
manner of presentation?
In Octavius' half of the debate, he proceeds eventually to the refutation of these slanders. Here are some of the
other things he says along the way.
In ridiculing the Greek myths about the deaths of their gods, such as Isis lamenting over the dismembered Osiris, he
says (22): "Is it not absurd to bewail what you worship, or worship what you bewail?" In other words, he is castigating the
Greeks for lamenting and worshiping a god who is slain. Later he says (23): "Men who have died cannot become gods, because
a god cannot die; nor can men who are born (become gods) . . . Why, I pray, are gods not born today, if such have ever been
born?" He then goes on to ridicule the whole idea of gods procreating themselves, which would include the idea of a god begetting
a son. Elsewhere (20) he scorns those who are credulous enough to believe in miracles performed by gods.
How, without any saving qualification, could a Christian put such arguments forward, since they would confute and
confound essential Christian beliefs in his own mind, and leave himself open to the charge of hypocrisy? It is one
thing for the puzzled commentator to claim that silences in the apologists are due to a desire not to discourage or irritate
the pagans with long and confusing theological treatises on subjects they are prejudiced against, or because they are not
aiming to provide a comprehensive picture of the faith. But when an apologist makes statements which flatly contradict and
even calumnize ideas which should be at the very heart of his own beliefs and personal devotion, such explanations are clearly
discredited.
And how does Minucius Felix deal with the accusation that Christians worship a crucified man and his cross? As he
did in Caecilius' diatribe, the author inserts his response into the midst of his refutation of other calumnies about incestuous
banquets and adoration of a priest's genitals. Here is the manner and context in which he deals with the charge of worshiping
a crucified criminal (29):
"1These
and similar indecencies we do not wish to hear; it is disgraceful having to defend ourselves from such charges. People who
live a chaste and virtuous life are falsely charged by you with acts which we would not consider possible, except that we
see you doing them yourselves. 2Moreover (nam), when you attribute to our religion
the worship of a criminal and his cross, you wander far from the truth in thinking that a criminal deserved, or that a mortal
man could be able, to be believed in as God. 3Miserable indeed is that man whose whole hope is dependent
on a mortal, for such hope ceases with his (the latter's) death . . . ."
Before going on, we should first note that verse 2, following as it does on the sentiments of verse 1 (which the Latin
word nam emphasizes), makes it clear that the writer regards this accusation as being in the same vein as the other
"indecencies" he is at pains to refute. And what is the refutation he provides? It is to heap scorn on those who would believe
that a crucified criminal, a mortal, should be thought of as a god. Where is the necessary qualification that no Christian
could surely have remained silent on? Where is the saving defence that in fact this crucified man was not a mortal, but was
indeed God? Some claim that this is what Minucius is implying, but such an implication is so opaque, it can only be derived
from reading it into the text. Octavius' words certainly do not contain it, although they do imply that the writer knows of
some Christians who believe such things, but he has no sympathy with them.
The translator of this work in the 19th century collection of Ante-Nicene Fathers (vol. IV, p.191) includes
the following sentence in his summary preface at the head of chapter 29: "For they believe not only that he was innocent,
but with reason that he was God." Such an idea is nowhere to be found in the text, and the context of the charge and its response
cannot reasonably be said to imply it. Nor do the other things Minucius says which scorn different aspects of the Christian
faith (such as gods being born in the present time or performing miracles) allow us to draw such an implication. To verse
2 the translator offers this wishful footnote: "A reverent allusion to the Crucified, believed in and worshiped as God." What
one cannot believe is missing, one will read into the text, no matter what.
A more recent commentator, G. W. Clarke (Ancient Christian Writers #39, 1949) makes this observation in an
end note: "A remarkable avoidance of any mention of the Incarnation. Indeed, so anxious is Minucius Felix to avoid admitting
such a difficult doctrine that he gives the appearance of denying it." Indeed he does. And while Clarke compares this to Arnobius'
"coyness" on the same topic, this later (c.300) Christian apologist was in no way reluctant or dishonest in admitting it,
even though he lived at a time of greater persecution. "We worship one who was born a man. What then? Do you worship no one
who was born a man? . . . But he died nailed to the cross. So what? Neither does the kind and disgrace of the death change
his words or deeds." (Against the Heathen, I.37 & 40).
Minucius goes on in this passage to cite the folly of heathen peoples who do "choose a man for their worship,"
but he makes no such admissions for Christians. As to the accusation of worshiping crosses, he says dismissively: "We do not
adore them, nor do we wish for them." And he goes on to admonish the pagan for being guilty of using signs of crosses in their
own worship and everyday life. There is not a hint that for Minucius the cross bears any sacred significance or requires defending
in a Christian context.
From this refutation of the calumny of Jesus and his cross, he proceeds ("Next . . .") to challenge those who accuse
Christians of the slaughter of children. There is nothing in the way Minucius has dealt with the supposed heart of the Christian
faith to differentiate it from all these surrounding horrors. The disparaging tone is unredeemed.
One commentator, H. J. Baylis (Minucius Felix, p.148), in addition to expressing his regret that the writer
has been so silent in defending the person of Christ, also laments the fact that he missed a golden opportunity to refute
the charge about licentious feasts and cannabilistic initiation rites by describing the Eucharist. He could have defended,
says Baylis, the sacramental significance and pure conduct of this Christian agape (love feast) over Jesus' body and
blood. Baylis finds it equally "odd" that in speaking of the sources of the "truth about the Godhead" (38), Minucius is silent
on the teachings of Jesus himself, or Jesus' own status as Son within that Godhead.
The survival of this document, with its out-and-out dismissal of the central tenets of Christianity, is perhaps surprising,
but it was no doubt possible only because a certain veiled ambiguity could be read into a verse like 29:2 above, and by letting
this perception override the derogatory tone and jarring silence of the passage and document as a whole. Baylis has labelled
29:2 "oblique," but Minucius' stark language rules out any such escape route. This scholar, too, reads into Minucius' defense
something which is not evidently there: "Yes, we adore one who was crucified, but he is neither a criminal nor a mere man."
Those who are capable of letting historical documents say what they obviously seem to be saying will recognize that
Minucius Felix is a true 'smoking gun' pointing to a Christian denial of the historical Jesus. Even though this document
indicates that there were others within the movement who believed in such a figure, and that there were historical Jesus traditions
circulating, this does not automatically validate the historicity of such a figure, especially as the author is writing no
earlier than the mid-second century. But the key consideration is this: such a denial as Minucius Felix voices would hardly
have been possible within the context of a movement which had actually begun with an historical Jesus, and so we can say that
this document does indeed provide strong evidence of the non-existence of this figure.
To the dispassionate eye, Minucius Felix is one Christian who will have no truck with those, in other circles of his
religion, who profess the worship of a Jesus who was crucified in Judea under the governorship of Pontius Pilate, rumors of which
have reached pagan ears and elicited much scorn and condemnation. To claim that a whole generation of apologists would falsely
convey such an exterior to those they are seeking to win over, that they would deliberately indulge in this kind of Machiavellian
deception, is but one of the desperate measures which modern Christian scholars have been forced to adopt in their efforts
to deal with a Christian record that stubbornly refuses to paint the picture they all want to see.
*
* *
*
The apologists were not fools. Their literary and polemical talents were considerable. They were versed in a wide
range of ancient knowledge, in the intricate subtleties of contemporary philosophy. That they could design careful and elaborate
pieces of apologetic writing that yet contained such devastating omissions and weaknesses as we have seen in Minucius Felix,
in Theophilus, in Athenagoras, in Tatian, is not feasible.
If an author like Minucius Felix is being silent for political reasons, why would he choose to place in the mouth
of his pagan spokesperson accusations concerning the very thing he is deliberately silent on? Why would he allow the opponent
such critical and derogatory declarations about the central object of Christian worship when he has already decided he must
deny himself the luxury of answering them? Why would he place in the Christian's own mouth, as he does in chapters
21 and 23, sweeping and scornful statements which go against elements of the Christian faith with no possibility of offering
saving qualifications? There is not even an attempt, through veiled language and implication, to assuage the 'knowing' Christian
reader, to show that such saving exceptions are present in his own mind. In fact, his treatment of these faith subjects is
tantamount to a denial of them.
At the end of Minucius Felix the writer has his pagan character converted to Christianity. But what is the
use of converting someone like Caecilius to a religion which has had all its essential elements concealed? When Caecilius
arrives "on the morrow" for his first lesson as a catechumen, will Octavius say to him, "Oh, by the way, there were a few
details I left out yesterday." If a Christian is going to appeal to a pagan according to philosophical and logical principles,
how will he then turn around and subsequently present the Christian mysteries and dogmas which he must be aware go counter
to such principles? His own argumentation will then be in danger of being turned against him. And his dishonesty will place
himself and his faith in a dishonorable light.
It must be stressed that nowhere in the literature of the time is there support for the standard scholarly rationalization
about the apologists' silence on the figure of Jesus. Nowhere is it discussed or even intimated that these writers have in
fact deliberately left out the essential elements of Christian faith in their defences of it, for reasons of political correctness
or anything else. The occasionally quoted account of Origen in the third century, that he sometimes expounded his ethical
views without labeling them as Christian, since he feared his listeners' hostility to the very name of Christianity and Christ,
is not applicable here, for in such cases Origen was not identifying himself as a Christian at all, he was not offering a
defence of Christianity, even in a limited way. If he had been, he would certainly not have left himself open to challenges
he was not allowed to answer. His own writings are proof of this. Origen does not conceal Jesus or his resurrection. He counters
every scoff and calumny of Celsus with all the resources at his disposal.
This is true also of Tertullian, writing his apology around the year 200 and borrowing, or at least using as inspiration,
parts of the work of Minucius Felix. Tertullian indulges in no such cryptic concealment. In his own day, the hostility to
Christianity was no easier than it had been a generation earlier when Felix wrote, or a mere two decades since Athenagoras
and Theophilus had penned their defences. Tertullian's work is full of vivid references to Christ's incarnation, to his death
and resurrection. Near the end of his account of "that Christ, the Son of God who appeared among us," he declares: "let no
one think it is otherwise than we have represented, for none may give a false account of his religion . . . . We say,
and before all men we say, and torn and bleeding under your tortures we cry out, 'We worhip God through Christ!' " Apparently,
if we believe the commentators, the bulk of the second century apologists possessed no such conviction, no such courage. Certainly,
Tertullian would have had no sympathy with their policy of concealment. The above quote may even be a veiled condemnation
of them, if he were familiar with the likes of Athenagoras or Tatian or Theophilus. Or it may have been directed at Minucius
Felix himself, whose work he would have felt constrained to expand on and fill in the painfully missing blanks.
As a final note, we might ask: where are the writers (for we might expect there to be some) who openly and in unmistakable
words reject the figure of Jesus, with no possibility of ambiguity? Until we realize that no such document would ever have
reached us through two millennia of Christian censorship. For probably the same reason, we possess no pagan writing which
discusses the case for rejection of the historical Jesus. Even Celsus (who does not do this) survives only piecemeal in Origen's
great refutation of him. On the other hand, it is likely that even leading pagan thinkers like Celsus would have had no way
to verify or disprove the circulating Christian story and narrative accounts of Jesus of Nazareth, nor would they have possessed
the exegetical tools and abilities to disprove Christian claims through a study of the documents themselves. In any case,
all of these documents, given the poor state of communication and availability of materials in the ancient world, would hardly
have been accessible to someone who might think of undertaking such a task. |
|
|
|