Home | Jeremy Bentham: His Life and Impact--jk | UTILITARIAN ETHICS: an introductory explanation | JAMES MILL ON RELIGION | BENTHAM ON BUGGERY, and other crimes against oneself | The Bentham Brothers, their adventure in Russia | Panopticon, Bentham's design of prisons | Bentham's final resting place | Bentham's Utilitarianism in Victorian England | Bentham, Life and Involvement with University College London | JOHN STUART MILL ON JEREMY BENTHAM | Bentham, a Deeper Look | John Stuart Mill: a brief account | Jeremy Bentham's Will | The Rationale of Reward--Bentham | BENTHAM: THE RATIONAL OF PUNISHMENT IMMORAL | BENTHAM: ON THE RATIONAL OF REWARD | JEREMY BENTHAM: Shorter Britannica Article | UTILITARIANISM - - John Stuart Mill | Taylor Harriet Mill | John Stuart Mill: a fuller account | Betham and His Works | Betham: A Short Accounting | Utilitarianism as adopted by theologians: a review | Utilitarianism, an historical survey | James Mill | Samuel Bentham | THE SPRINGS OF ACTION--Jeremy Bentham | JEREMY BENTHAM ON PLEASURE | Prof. Singer, the utilitarian, 2 articles | UTILITARIAN LINKS
UTILITARIANISM: the ethical theory for all times.
BENTHAM: THE RATIONAL OF PUNISHMENT IMMORAL

Bentham used utilitarianism primarily as a measure of the moral rightness of law and of social mores. He also applied this principle to the acts of individual--though he wrote much less thereon.

ENLIGHTENMENT

BY JEREMY BENTHAM:

The Rationale of Punishment.

Book I
General Principles
Chapter III
Of the Ends of Punishment
When any act has been committed which is followed, or threatens to be followed, by such effects as a provident legislator would be anxious to prevent, two wishes naturally and immediately suggest themselves to his mind: first, to obviate the danger of the like mischief in future: secondly, to compensate the mischief that has already been done.

The mischief likely to ensue from acts of the like kind may arise from either of two sources,either the conduct of the party himself who has been the author of the mischief already done, or the conduct of such other persons as may have adequate motives and sufficient opportunities to do the like.

Hence the prevention of offenses divides itself into two branches: Particular prevention, which applies to the delinquent himself; and general prevention, which is applicable to all the members of the community without exception.

Pain and pleasure are the great springs of human action. When a man perceives or supposes pain to be the consequence of an act, he is acted upon in such a manner as tends, with a certain force, to withdraw him, as it were, from the commission of that act. If the apparent magnitude, or rather value of that pain be greater than the apparent magnitude or value of the pleasure or good he expects to be the consequence of the act, he will be absolutely prevented from performing it. The mischief which would have ensued from the act, if performed, will also by that means be prevented.

With respect to a given individual, the recurrence of an offense may be provided against in three ways:

By taking from him the physical power of offending.
By taking away the desire of offending.
By making him afraid of offending.

In the first case, the individual can no more commit the offense; in the second, he no longer desires to commit it; in the third, he may still wish to commit it, but he no longer dares to do it. In the first case, there is a physical incapacity; in the second, a moral reformation; in the third, there is intimidation or terror of the law.

General prevention is effected by the denunciation of punishment, and by its application, which, according to the common expression, serves for an example. The punishment suffered by the offender presents to every one an example of what he himself will have to suffer if he is guilty of the same offense..

General prevention ought to be the chief end of punishment, as it is its real justification. If we could consider an offence which has been committed as an isolated fact, the like of which would never recur, punishment would be useless. It would be only adding one evil to another. But when we consider that an unpunished crime leaves the path of crime open not only to the same delinquent, but also to all those who may have the same motives and opportunities for entering upon it, we perceive that the punishment inflicted on the individual becomes a source of security to all. That punishment, which, considered in itself, appeared base and repugnant to all generous sentiments, is elevated to the first rank of benefits, when it is regarded not as an act of wrath or of vengeance against a guilty or unfortunate individual who has given way to mischievous inclinations, but as an indispensable sacrifice to the common safety.

With respect to any particular delinquent, we have seen that punishment has three objects, incapacitation, reformation, and intimidation. If the crime he has committed is of a kind calculated to inspire great alarm, as manifesting a very mischievous disposition, it becomes necessary to take from him the power of committing it again. But if the crime, being less dangerous, only justifies a transient punishment, and it is possible for the delinquent to return to society, it is proper that the punishment should possess qualities calculated to reform or to intimidate him.

After having provided for the prevention of future crimes, reparation still remains to be made, as far as possible, for those which are passed, by bestowing a compensation on the party injured; that is to say, bestowing a good equal to the evil suffered.

This compensation, founded upon reasons which have been elsewhere developed, does not at first view appear to belong to the subject of punishments, because it concerns another individual than the delinquent. But these two ends have a real connexion. There are punishments which have the double effect of affording compensation to the party injured, and of inflicting a proportionate suffering on the delinquent; so that these two ends may be effected by a single operation. This is, in certain cases, the peculiar advantage of pecuniary punishments.


powered by lycos
SEARCH:Tripod The Web

"Pain and pleasure are the great springs of human action" Bentham writes above. This was stated by Epicures, ("for without pleasure we do all to get it back" in his maxims"). But it was not until Watson and then B. F. Skinner that this understanding was developed into the most insightful analysis of human behavior. (I will be publishing a link to my improvements of behaviorism.)